首页 > 最新文献

Argumenta Philosophica最新文献

英文 中文
Riflessioni sul concetto di natura in Lucio Anneo Seneca 对自然概念的思考
Q4 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2019-01-01 DOI: 10.30687/978-88-6969-325-0/005
M. Cassan
The aim of this short paper is to highlight nature’s central role in the constitution and progress of human morality, by analysing nature’s multiple characters as displayed in various sections of Seneca’s work. First, the focus will extend to man’s fundamental propensity to good, which belongs to him by nature. Secondly, a virtuous and happy life will be presented as the life led according to nature. In conclusion, research on natural phenomena will be accounted for, as a building block towards moral perfection. The relationship between all the previous traits, mentioned in the cited passages, constitutes the heart of Seneca’s ethical naturalism.
这篇短文的目的是通过分析塞内加作品中各个部分所表现的自然的多重特征,来突出自然在人类道德的构成和进步中的核心作用。首先,重点将扩展到人类向善的基本倾向,这是天生属于他的。其次,一种美德和幸福的生活将呈现为按照自然的生活。总之,对自然现象的研究将作为道德完善的基石。上述段落中提到的上述所有特征之间的关系,构成了塞内加伦理自然主义的核心。
{"title":"Riflessioni sul concetto di natura in Lucio Anneo Seneca","authors":"M. Cassan","doi":"10.30687/978-88-6969-325-0/005","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.30687/978-88-6969-325-0/005","url":null,"abstract":"The aim of this short paper is to highlight nature’s central role in the constitution and progress of human morality, by analysing nature’s multiple characters as displayed in various sections of Seneca’s work. First, the focus will extend to man’s fundamental propensity to good, which belongs to him by nature. Secondly, a virtuous and happy life will be presented as the life led according to nature. In conclusion, research on natural phenomena will be accounted for, as a building block towards moral perfection. The relationship between all the previous traits, mentioned in the cited passages, constitutes the heart of Seneca’s ethical naturalism.","PeriodicalId":36843,"journal":{"name":"Argumenta Philosophica","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2019-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"86175677","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
La Natura e il Metodo 自然和方法
Q4 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2019-01-01 DOI: 10.30687/978-88-6969-325-0/008
Luigi Emilio Pischedda
The naturalistic approach to knowledge, as emerges from of Quine’s and Sellars’ works, puts an absolute trust in the way science operates, insomuch that it suggests that philosophy should adopt its criteria and methods. This subsumption of philosophy to science is possible only reducing every discourse on their relationship to a mere question of method. This article aims to point out, by using Spinoza’s thought, the possibility of an escape from this rigid dichotomy. For the Dutch philosopher the study of nature is, in fact, the occasion for a broader consideration on the possibilities of knowledge in contributing to the achievement of an authentic freedom.
从奎因和塞拉斯的著作中涌现出来的自然主义知识方法,绝对信任科学的运作方式,因此它建议哲学应该采用科学的标准和方法。把哲学归入科学,只有把关于哲学与科学的关系的论述简化为单纯的方法问题,才是可能的。本文旨在利用斯宾诺莎的思想,指出摆脱这种僵化的二分法的可能性。对于这位荷兰哲学家来说,对自然的研究实际上是对知识的可能性进行更广泛考虑的机会,有助于实现真正的自由。
{"title":"La Natura e il Metodo","authors":"Luigi Emilio Pischedda","doi":"10.30687/978-88-6969-325-0/008","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.30687/978-88-6969-325-0/008","url":null,"abstract":"The naturalistic approach to knowledge, as emerges from of Quine’s and Sellars’ works, puts an absolute trust in the way science operates, insomuch that it suggests that philosophy should adopt its criteria and methods. This subsumption of philosophy to science is possible only reducing every discourse on their relationship to a mere question of method. This article aims to point out, by using Spinoza’s thought, the possibility of an escape from this rigid dichotomy. For the Dutch philosopher the study of nature is, in fact, the occasion for a broader consideration on the possibilities of knowledge in contributing to the achievement of an authentic freedom.","PeriodicalId":36843,"journal":{"name":"Argumenta Philosophica","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2019-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"74629575","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Explanatory emergence as a guide to metaphysical structure 解释性涌现作为形而上学结构的指南
Q4 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2017-01-02 DOI: 10.21825/philosophica.82116
Elanor Taylor
The view that there is a distinction between strong, or metaphysical, emergence and weak, or explanatory, emergence, is widely accepted. It is natural, on this view, to regard accounts of strong and of weak emergence as performing different kinds of work, such that strong conceptions of emergence help us to uncover metaphysical structure, while weak conceptions of emergence help us to understand the limits of our scientific explanations. If we accept this division of labor, then it appears that we cannot use an account of weak, explanatory emergence to find out about metaphysical structure. In this paper, I explore the view that explanatory conceptions of emergence cannot be used for metaphysical purposes, and argue that it is false. Even those who reject strong emergence can, at least in principle, use certain explanatory accounts of emergence as guides to metaphysical structure. On this approach, emergence itself is explanatory, but explanatory emergence may sometimes obtain for metaphysical reasons.
人们普遍接受的观点是,强的或形而上的涌现和弱的或解释性的涌现是有区别的。根据这种观点,将强涌现和弱涌现的描述视为不同类型的工作是很自然的,例如,强涌现概念帮助我们揭示形而上学结构,而弱涌现概念帮助我们理解科学解释的局限性。如果我们接受这种分工,那么我们似乎就不能用一种弱的、解释性的涌现来发现形而上学的结构。在本文中,我探讨了出现的解释性概念不能用于形而上学目的的观点,并认为这是错误的。即使是那些反对强涌现论的人,至少在原则上,也可以使用某些关于涌现论的解释,作为形而上学结构的指导。在这种方法中,涌现本身是解释性的,但解释性的涌现有时可能出于形而上学的原因而获得。
{"title":"Explanatory emergence as a guide to metaphysical structure","authors":"Elanor Taylor","doi":"10.21825/philosophica.82116","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21825/philosophica.82116","url":null,"abstract":"The view that there is a distinction between strong, or metaphysical, emergence and weak, or explanatory, emergence, is widely accepted. It is natural, on this view, to regard accounts of strong and of weak emergence as performing different kinds of work, such that strong conceptions of emergence help us to uncover metaphysical structure, while weak conceptions of emergence help us to understand the limits of our scientific explanations. If we accept this division of labor, then it appears that we cannot use an account of weak, explanatory emergence to find out about metaphysical structure. In this paper, I explore the view that explanatory conceptions of emergence cannot be used for metaphysical purposes, and argue that it is false. Even those who reject strong emergence can, at least in principle, use certain explanatory accounts of emergence as guides to metaphysical structure. On this approach, emergence itself is explanatory, but explanatory emergence may sometimes obtain for metaphysical reasons.","PeriodicalId":36843,"journal":{"name":"Argumenta Philosophica","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2017-01-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"87182431","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Strong emergence 强大的出现
Q4 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2017-01-02 DOI: 10.21825/philosophica.82115
Alexander D. Carruth, J. T. Miller
A crucial question for both philosophy and for science concerns the kind of relationship that obtains between entities—objects, properties, states, processes, kinds and so on—that exist at apparently higher and lower ‘levels’ of reality. According to reductionism, seeming higher-level entities can in fact be fully accounted for by more fundamental, lower-level entities. Conversely, emergentists of various stripes hold that whilst higher-level entities depend in some important sense on lower-level entities, they are nevertheless irreducible to them. This introductory paper outlines the context of the debate between emergentists and reductionists; offers a broad characterisation of ‘strong’ or ontological emergence, and provides summaries of each of the papers to come in this special issue. 6 A. D. CARRUTH AND J.T.M. MILLER 1. The structure of inquiry and the structure of the world Part of the job of scientific inquiry is to engage with, make sense of, describe, explain and make predictions concerning the wildly varied phenomena which constitute the world around us. As a consequence of this aforementioned variety, distinct disciplines each with their own intellectual regimes—domains of inquiry, basic assumptions, investigative techniques and so on—address different groupings of this phenomena. Thus, physics, or at least an important part of that discipline, is concerned with the properties of and interactions between the relatively small and simple constituents of matter, and of energy. Chemistry addresses more complexly structured systems of those constituents that form substances—in the standard, as opposed to technical metaphysical, sense: elements, compounds, mixtures, suspensions and so on. Biology treats phenomena which exhibit the characteristics which are criterial for life, ranging over micro-organisms, flora, fauna etc. Psychology and cognitive science engage with just those living things which possess mentality, and sociology, economics and political science all range over aspects of the interactions between these thinking agents. These characterisations are somewhat glib, and they surely fall short of a properly nuanced and comprehensive conception of each discipline, but hopefully they are fit for the illustrative purpose to which they are employed. That inquiry has this sort of structure raises a number of interesting philosophical questions. One such set of questions concerns the sorts of relationships that obtain between the theories put forward by each discipline. Another set of questions concerns the extent to which the sort of structure described above is a feature not just of the way we organise our inquiry into the world, but of the world itself: that is, addressing the
对于哲学和科学来说,一个至关重要的问题涉及实体之间的关系——对象、性质、状态、过程、种类等等——它们显然存在于更高和更低的现实“层次”上。根据还原论,表面上更高层次的实体实际上可以被更基本、更低层次的实体完全解释。相反,各种各样的涌现主义者认为,虽然更高层次的实体在某种重要意义上依赖于较低层次的实体,但它们仍然不可约为它们。这篇介绍性的论文概述了紧急论者和简化论者之间争论的背景;提供了“强”或本体论涌现的广泛特征,并提供了本特刊中每篇论文的摘要。6个。D.卡鲁斯和J.T.M.米勒探究的结构和世界的结构科学探究的一部分工作是参与、理解、描述、解释和预测构成我们周围世界的各种各样的现象。由于前面提到的多样性,不同的学科都有自己的知识体系——探究领域、基本假设、调查技术等等——来处理这一现象的不同分组。因此,物理学,或者至少是该学科的一个重要部分,关注的是物质和能量的相对小而简单的组成部分的性质和相互作用。化学研究的是那些构成物质的成分的更复杂的结构系统——在标准意义上,与技术形而上学的意义相反:元素、化合物、混合物、悬浮液等等。生物学研究表现出生命标准特征的现象,包括微生物、植物、动物等。心理学和认知科学只研究那些具有心理的生物,社会学、经济学和政治学都涉及这些思维主体之间相互作用的各个方面。这些描述有些油滑,而且它们肯定缺乏对每个学科的适当细致和全面的概念,但希望它们适合于使用它们的说明性目的。这种结构的探究提出了许多有趣的哲学问题。其中一组问题涉及各个学科提出的理论之间的各种关系。另一组问题涉及到上述结构在多大程度上不仅是我们组织探索世界的方式的一个特征,也是世界本身的一个特征:也就是说,解决问题
{"title":"Strong emergence","authors":"Alexander D. Carruth, J. T. Miller","doi":"10.21825/philosophica.82115","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21825/philosophica.82115","url":null,"abstract":"A crucial question for both philosophy and for science concerns the kind of relationship that obtains between entities—objects, properties, states, processes, kinds and so on—that exist at apparently higher and lower ‘levels’ of reality. According to reductionism, seeming higher-level entities can in fact be fully accounted for by more fundamental, lower-level entities. Conversely, emergentists of various stripes hold that whilst higher-level entities depend in some important sense on lower-level entities, they are nevertheless irreducible to them. This introductory paper outlines the context of the debate between emergentists and reductionists; offers a broad characterisation of ‘strong’ or ontological emergence, and provides summaries of each of the papers to come in this special issue. 6 A. D. CARRUTH AND J.T.M. MILLER 1. The structure of inquiry and the structure of the world Part of the job of scientific inquiry is to engage with, make sense of, describe, explain and make predictions concerning the wildly varied phenomena which constitute the world around us. As a consequence of this aforementioned variety, distinct disciplines each with their own intellectual regimes—domains of inquiry, basic assumptions, investigative techniques and so on—address different groupings of this phenomena. Thus, physics, or at least an important part of that discipline, is concerned with the properties of and interactions between the relatively small and simple constituents of matter, and of energy. Chemistry addresses more complexly structured systems of those constituents that form substances—in the standard, as opposed to technical metaphysical, sense: elements, compounds, mixtures, suspensions and so on. Biology treats phenomena which exhibit the characteristics which are criterial for life, ranging over micro-organisms, flora, fauna etc. Psychology and cognitive science engage with just those living things which possess mentality, and sociology, economics and political science all range over aspects of the interactions between these thinking agents. These characterisations are somewhat glib, and they surely fall short of a properly nuanced and comprehensive conception of each discipline, but hopefully they are fit for the illustrative purpose to which they are employed. That inquiry has this sort of structure raises a number of interesting philosophical questions. One such set of questions concerns the sorts of relationships that obtain between the theories put forward by each discipline. Another set of questions concerns the extent to which the sort of structure described above is a feature not just of the way we organise our inquiry into the world, but of the world itself: that is, addressing the","PeriodicalId":36843,"journal":{"name":"Argumenta Philosophica","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2017-01-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"75109550","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Manipulationism and causal exclusion 操纵主义和因果排除
Q4 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2017-01-02 DOI: 10.21825/philosophica.82110
M. Pexton
A new way of avoiding the causal exclusion argument in the context of manipulationism is proposed. In manipulationism, causal explanations are defined by counterfactual information accessed through manipulations. It is argued that the property of manipulability can be an emergent property of aggregate systems. Therefore, some causal explanations are non-reducible and causal exclusion is avoided. This emergentist notion of causal explanation addresses the question of how the special sciences can be based upon causal reasoning, even if fundamental physics is absent of causal relations.
提出了一种在操纵主义背景下避免因果排斥论点的新方法。在操纵主义中,因果解释是通过操纵获得的反事实信息来定义的。论证了可操作性的性质可以是聚集系统的一个涌现性质。因此,一些因果解释是不可约的,避免了因果排斥。这种因果解释的涌现主义概念解决了这样一个问题:即使基础物理学缺乏因果关系,特殊科学如何能够基于因果推理。
{"title":"Manipulationism and causal exclusion","authors":"M. Pexton","doi":"10.21825/philosophica.82110","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21825/philosophica.82110","url":null,"abstract":"A new way of avoiding the causal exclusion argument in the context of manipulationism is proposed. In manipulationism, causal explanations are defined by counterfactual information accessed through manipulations. It is argued that the property of manipulability can be an emergent property of aggregate systems. Therefore, some causal explanations are non-reducible and causal exclusion is avoided. This emergentist notion of causal explanation addresses the question of how the special sciences can be based upon causal reasoning, even if fundamental physics is absent of causal relations.","PeriodicalId":36843,"journal":{"name":"Argumenta Philosophica","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2017-01-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"73944453","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Strong emergence and downward causation in biological physics 生物物理学中的强涌现和向下因果关系
Q4 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2017-01-02 DOI: 10.21825/philosophica.82113
T. McLeish
The methodological lens of physics within the realm of biology creates the interdisciplinary field of Biological Physics: a fruitful one with which to explore the idea of Strong Emergence. Examples of emergent entities are found in: e.g. protein assembly within cell membranes, gene expression from external cell signalling, topological interaction of DNA and topoisomerase enzymes. The flow of information (itself determined by constraints) is urged as an indicator for downward causation. Strongly emergent structures carry information at high (larger scale) level that is not constituted by the sum of information at low (smaller scale) levels. Biological physics throws empirical light on the metaphysical question of downward causation without having to broach the additional complexities and contested qualities of the mental. 114 T. C. B. McLEISH
生物学领域内的物理学方法论视角创造了生物物理学的跨学科领域:一个探索强涌现思想的富有成效的领域。涌现实体的例子包括:细胞膜内的蛋白质组装,细胞外部信号的基因表达,DNA和拓扑异构酶的拓扑相互作用。信息流(本身由约束决定)被敦促作为向下因果关系的指示。强突现结构在高水平(更大规模)上携带信息,而这些信息不是由低水平(更小规模)上的信息总和构成的。生物物理学将经验的光芒投射到向下因果关系的形而上学问题上,而不必触及额外的复杂性和有争议的精神品质。114 t.c.b.麦克利什
{"title":"Strong emergence and downward causation in biological physics","authors":"T. McLeish","doi":"10.21825/philosophica.82113","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21825/philosophica.82113","url":null,"abstract":"The methodological lens of physics within the realm of biology creates the interdisciplinary field of Biological Physics: a fruitful one with which to explore the idea of Strong Emergence. Examples of emergent entities are found in: e.g. protein assembly within cell membranes, gene expression from external cell signalling, topological interaction of DNA and topoisomerase enzymes. The flow of information (itself determined by constraints) is urged as an indicator for downward causation. Strongly emergent structures carry information at high (larger scale) level that is not constituted by the sum of information at low (smaller scale) levels. Biological physics throws empirical light on the metaphysical question of downward causation without having to broach the additional complexities and contested qualities of the mental. 114 T. C. B. McLEISH","PeriodicalId":36843,"journal":{"name":"Argumenta Philosophica","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2017-01-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"77620982","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 3
Language and ontological emergence 语言与本体论涌现
Q4 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2017-01-02 DOI: 10.21825/philosophica.82118
James Miller
Pre-Proof Version; Please cite final version forthcoming in Philosophica Abstract: Providing empirically supportable instances of ontological emergence is notoriously difficult. Typically, the literature has focused on two possible sources. The first is the mind and consciousness; the second is within physics, and more specifically certain quantum effects. In this paper, I wish to suggest that the literature has overlooked a further possible instance of emergence, taken from the special science of linguistics. In particular, I will focus on the property of truth-evaluability, taken to be a property of sentences as created by the language faculty within human minds (or brains). The claim will not be as strong as to suggest that the linguistic data and theories prove emergence. Rather the dialectical aim here is to say that we have some good reasons (even if not conclusive reasons) to think that the property is emergent.
Pre-Proof版本;摘要:提供本体论涌现的经验支持实例是出了名的困难。通常,文献集中在两个可能的来源。首先是心灵和意识;第二个是在物理学内部,更具体地说,是某些量子效应。在本文中,我想指出的是,这些文献忽略了另一个可能的涌现例子,它来自语言学这门特殊的科学。特别地,我将集中讨论真值可评估性的特性,它被认为是由人类思想(或大脑)中的语言能力创造的句子的特性。这种说法还没有强到足以证明语言数据和理论证明了涌现。相反,这里辩证的目的是说,我们有一些很好的理由(即使不是结论性的理由)认为属性是涌现的。
{"title":"Language and ontological emergence","authors":"James Miller","doi":"10.21825/philosophica.82118","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21825/philosophica.82118","url":null,"abstract":"Pre-Proof Version; Please cite final version forthcoming in Philosophica Abstract: Providing empirically supportable instances of ontological emergence is notoriously difficult. Typically, the literature has focused on two possible sources. The first is the mind and consciousness; the second is within physics, and more specifically certain quantum effects. In this paper, I wish to suggest that the literature has overlooked a further possible instance of emergence, taken from the special science of linguistics. In particular, I will focus on the property of truth-evaluability, taken to be a property of sentences as created by the language faculty within human minds (or brains). The claim will not be as strong as to suggest that the linguistic data and theories prove emergence. Rather the dialectical aim here is to say that we have some good reasons (even if not conclusive reasons) to think that the property is emergent.","PeriodicalId":36843,"journal":{"name":"Argumenta Philosophica","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2017-01-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"88307137","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Strong emergence no, contextual emergence yes 强烈涌现不是,情境涌现是
Q4 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2017-01-02 DOI: 10.21825/philosophica.82119
M. Silberstein
It will be argued that strong/radical emergence while possible is problematic on a number of fronts, in particular it is neither explanatory nor unifying. Fortunately, there is a better, more unifying and explanatory alternative that be will called contextual emergence. The notion of contextual emergence will be explicated and defended against competitors.
有人会说,强烈/激进的出现虽然可能,但在许多方面都是有问题的,特别是它既不能解释也不能统一。幸运的是,有一个更好、更统一、更能解释的选择,他将其称为情境涌现。上下文涌现的概念将被解释和辩护,以对抗竞争对手。
{"title":"Strong emergence no, contextual emergence yes","authors":"M. Silberstein","doi":"10.21825/philosophica.82119","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21825/philosophica.82119","url":null,"abstract":"It will be argued that strong/radical emergence while possible is problematic on a number of fronts, in particular it is neither explanatory nor unifying. Fortunately, there is a better, more unifying and explanatory alternative that be will called contextual emergence. The notion of contextual emergence will be explicated and defended against competitors.","PeriodicalId":36843,"journal":{"name":"Argumenta Philosophica","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2017-01-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"79531466","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 4
Must strong emergence collapse? 强涌现一定会崩溃吗?
Q4 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2017-01-02 DOI: 10.21825/philosophica.82117
Umut Baysan, Jessica M. Wilson
There have recently been complaints from various quarters that strong emergence doesn’t make sense, on grounds that any purportedly strongly emergent features or associated powers can be se en to ‘collapse’, one way or another, into the lower - level base features upon which they depend. On one version of this collapse objection, certain ways of individuating lower - level physical features entail that such features will have dispositions to prod uce any purportedly strongly emergent features, undermining the supposed metaphysical novelty of the emergent features and the physical acceptability of the base features (see Howell 2009 and Taylor 2015). On another, certain ways of assigning powers to fe atures entail that lower - level physical features will inherit any powers had by purportedly strongly emergent features (see Kim, 1998 and 2006, and others). Here we present and defend four different responses that might be given to the collapse objection a s directed against a ‘novel power’ approach to strong emergence: first, distinguishing between direct and indirect having of powers; second, distinguishing between lightweight and heavyweight dispositions; third, taking strong emergence to be relative to s ets of fundamental interactions; fourth, taking strongly emergent features to be ‘new object entailing’, in ways that block lower - level inheritance of powers.
最近有来自各个方面的抱怨,认为强涌现是没有意义的,理由是任何据称强涌现的特征或相关的力量都可以被视为以这样或那样的方式“崩溃”为它们所依赖的较低层次的基本特征。在这种崩溃反对的一个版本中,个性化较低层次物理特征的某些方式意味着,这些特征将有可能产生任何据称强烈的涌现特征,从而破坏了涌现特征的所谓形而上学新颖性和基本特征的物理可接受性(见Howell 2009和Taylor 2015)。另一方面,某些赋予特征权力的方式意味着较低层次的物理特征将继承据称是强烈涌现特征所拥有的任何权力(见Kim, 1998和2006等)。在这里,我们提出并捍卫了四种不同的回应,这些回应可能会对反对“新权力”方法的崩溃提出异议:首先,区分直接和间接拥有权力;第二,区分轻量级和重量级的性格;第三,将强涌现与五组基本相互作用相关联;第四,以阻止较低层次的权力继承的方式,将强烈涌现的特征视为“新对象的必然”。
{"title":"Must strong emergence collapse?","authors":"Umut Baysan, Jessica M. Wilson","doi":"10.21825/philosophica.82117","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21825/philosophica.82117","url":null,"abstract":"There have recently been complaints from various quarters that strong \u0000emergence doesn’t make sense, on grounds that any purportedly strongly \u0000emergent features or associated powers can be se \u0000en to ‘collapse’, one way or \u0000another, into the lower \u0000- \u0000level base features upon which they depend. On one \u0000version of this collapse objection, certain ways of individuating lower \u0000- \u0000level \u0000physical features entail that such features will have dispositions to prod \u0000uce any \u0000purportedly strongly emergent features, undermining the supposed \u0000metaphysical novelty of the emergent features and the physical acceptability of \u0000the base features (see Howell 2009 and Taylor 2015). On another, certain ways of \u0000assigning powers to fe \u0000atures entail that lower \u0000- \u0000level physical features will inherit \u0000any powers had by purportedly strongly emergent features (see Kim, 1998 and \u00002006, and others). Here we present and defend four different responses that \u0000might be given to the collapse objection a \u0000s directed against a ‘novel power’ \u0000approach to strong emergence: first, distinguishing between direct and indirect \u0000having of powers; second, distinguishing between lightweight and heavyweight \u0000dispositions; third, taking strong emergence to be relative to s \u0000ets of fundamental \u0000interactions; fourth, taking strongly emergent features to be ‘new object \u0000entailing’, in ways that block lower \u0000- \u0000level inheritance of powers.","PeriodicalId":36843,"journal":{"name":"Argumenta Philosophica","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2017-01-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"73761876","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 16
Topological order and emergence 拓扑秩序与涌现
Q4 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2017-01-02 DOI: 10.21825/philosophica.82112
J. Bain
Topologically ordered systems play a prominent role in current research in condensed matter physics; examples include systems that exhibit the quantum Hall effect, topological insulators, and topological superconductors. These systems possess properties that are characterized by topological invariants, exhibit phase transitions that cannot be characterized by spontaneous symmetry breaking, and exhibit order that cannot be characterized in terms of a local order parameter. They thus fall outside the scope of the Landau–Ginsburg theory of phase transitions, which, arguably, has informed much of the discussion, in both the physics and philosophy literature, of emergence in condensed matter systems. Nevertheless, some authors have claimed that topologically ordered systems exhibit emergence. This essay offers a critical assessment of this claim. In particular, it identifies two types of topological order and observes that, whereas the alleged mechanisms underwriting these types differ, they nevertheless share certain features; in particular, the lowenergy behavior of such systems can be described by effective topological quantum field theories. This suggests that a unified account of the emergence of topological order should look to a law-centric, as opposed to a mechanismcentric, view of emergence.
拓扑有序系统在凝聚态物理研究中占有重要地位;例子包括表现出量子霍尔效应、拓扑绝缘体和拓扑超导体的系统。这些系统具有以拓扑不变量为特征的特性,表现出不能用自发对称性破缺来表征的相变,以及表现出不能用局部顺序参数来表征的秩序。因此,它们不在朗道-金斯堡相变理论的范围之内,而在物理学和哲学文献中,关于凝聚态系统中出现的讨论,可以说是由朗道-金斯堡相变理论引起的。然而,一些作者声称拓扑有序系统表现出涌现。本文对这一说法进行了批判性的评估。特别是,它确定了两种类型的拓扑秩序,并观察到,尽管所谓的机制支持这些类型不同,但它们仍然具有某些特征;特别是,这种系统的低能量行为可以用有效拓扑量子场论来描述。这表明,对拓扑秩序出现的统一解释应该着眼于以法律为中心,而不是以机制为中心的出现观。
{"title":"Topological order and emergence","authors":"J. Bain","doi":"10.21825/philosophica.82112","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21825/philosophica.82112","url":null,"abstract":"Topologically ordered systems play a prominent role in current research in condensed matter physics; examples include systems that exhibit the quantum Hall effect, topological insulators, and topological superconductors. These systems possess properties that are characterized by topological invariants, exhibit phase transitions that cannot be characterized by spontaneous symmetry breaking, and exhibit order that cannot be characterized in terms of a local order parameter. They thus fall outside the scope of the Landau–Ginsburg theory of phase transitions, which, arguably, has informed much of the discussion, in both the physics and philosophy literature, of emergence in condensed matter systems. Nevertheless, some authors have claimed that topologically ordered systems exhibit emergence. This essay offers a critical assessment of this claim. In particular, it identifies two types of topological order and observes that, whereas the alleged mechanisms underwriting these types differ, they nevertheless share certain features; in particular, the lowenergy behavior of such systems can be described by effective topological quantum field theories. This suggests that a unified account of the emergence of topological order should look to a law-centric, as opposed to a mechanismcentric, view of emergence.","PeriodicalId":36843,"journal":{"name":"Argumenta Philosophica","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2017-01-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"74938578","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
期刊
Argumenta Philosophica
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1