首页 > 最新文献

Argumenta Philosophica最新文献

英文 中文
Exorcizing Demons: Thomas Hobbes and Balthasar Bekker on Spirits and Religion 《驱魔:托马斯·霍布斯和巴尔萨萨·贝克论精神与宗教》
Q4 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2014-01-02 DOI: 10.21825/philosophica.82126
Alissa MacMillan
Thomas Hobbes devotes several chapters of Leviathan to a careful critique of belief in, and the uses and abuses of, demons, ghosts, and spirits. But his broader views on religion remain one of the more contested areas of his thought, leaving his role in the ‘Radical Enlightenment’ unclear. A thoroughgoing opposition to demons and ghosts was also one of the primary objectives of Dutch theologian Balthasar Bekker, a figure whose central role in the historical narrative on atheism is well defended and accounted for in Jonathan Israel’s Radical Enlightenment. Bekker was loudly declared an atheist of the worst sort, that is, of the Hobbesian or Spinozist sort. This paper engages an analysis and comparison of their respective treatments of demons and ghosts, elucidating several of the real differences in their views, and arguing that Hobbes’s critique of religion, one on the surface one quite similar in spirit to that of Bekker, is indeed the more ‘radical’ when considered in light of their distinctive epistemologies, arguments for God, and the main thrust of their projects. Alongside Bekker, the innovative elements of Hobbes’s critique of religion become especially clear.
托马斯·霍布斯在《利维坦》中花了几章的篇幅,仔细批判了对恶魔、鬼魂和灵魂的信仰,以及对它们的使用和滥用。但他关于宗教的更广泛的观点仍然是他思想中更有争议的领域之一,这使得他在“激进启蒙运动”中的角色不明朗。彻底反对恶魔和鬼魂也是荷兰神学家巴尔萨萨·贝克(Balthasar Bekker)的主要目标之一,他在无神论历史叙事中的核心作用在乔纳森·伊斯雷尔(Jonathan Israel)的《激进启蒙运动》(Radical Enlightenment)一书中得到了很好的辩护和解释。贝克被大声宣布为最坏的一类无神论者,也就是霍布斯或斯宾诺莎一类的无神论者。本文对他们各自对待恶魔和鬼魂的方式进行了分析和比较,阐明了他们观点中的几个真正的差异,并认为霍布斯对宗教的批判,表面上与贝克的批判在精神上非常相似,当考虑到他们独特的认识论、对上帝的论证和他们项目的主要动力时,确实是更“激进”的。与贝克一起,霍布斯对宗教批判的创新元素变得尤为明显。
{"title":"Exorcizing Demons: Thomas Hobbes and Balthasar Bekker on Spirits and Religion","authors":"Alissa MacMillan","doi":"10.21825/philosophica.82126","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21825/philosophica.82126","url":null,"abstract":"Thomas Hobbes devotes several chapters of Leviathan to a careful critique of belief in, and the uses and abuses of, demons, ghosts, and spirits. But his broader views on religion remain one of the more contested areas of his thought, leaving his role in the ‘Radical Enlightenment’ unclear. A thoroughgoing opposition to demons and ghosts was also one of the primary objectives of Dutch theologian Balthasar Bekker, a figure whose central role in the historical narrative on atheism is well defended and accounted for in Jonathan Israel’s Radical Enlightenment. Bekker was loudly declared an atheist of the worst sort, that is, of the Hobbesian or Spinozist sort. This paper engages an analysis and comparison of their respective treatments of demons and ghosts, elucidating several of the real differences in their views, and arguing that Hobbes’s critique of religion, one on the surface one quite similar in spirit to that of Bekker, is indeed the more ‘radical’ when considered in light of their distinctive epistemologies, arguments for God, and the main thrust of their projects. Alongside Bekker, the innovative elements of Hobbes’s critique of religion become especially clear.","PeriodicalId":36843,"journal":{"name":"Argumenta Philosophica","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2014-01-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"83742800","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
Radical Enlightenment, Enlightened Subversion, and Spinoza 激进启蒙,开明颠覆,以及斯宾诺莎
Q4 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2014-01-02 DOI: 10.21825/philosophica.82127
S. Lavaert
An important philosophical turn that took place in seventeenthand eighteenth-century Enlightenment thought was the abandonment of transcendence, the strict separation of religion and philosophy, and the rise of a one-substance immanent ontology. It has been argued that this ‘radical’ turn brought about the philosophical foundation for democracy. According to the thesis I will defend in what follows, immanent ontology indeed has a political subversive meaning. Inspired by the texts and ideas of Machiavelli, it entailed a radical change of focus: from a theologicalhierarchical structure to the horizontal structure of the world in which we live and in which all humans are equal. This radical change had consequences at the level of the civil state: e.g., the necessity of free thought and free speech, which may lead to resistance, refusal, and disobedience. I will argue that this Spinozistic radicalism can only be adequately understood if we take into account the radical thought of fellow thinkers from his circle, on the one hand, and the subversive image of Spinoza as constructed by his opponents on the other.
在17和18世纪启蒙思想中,一个重要的哲学转向是放弃了先验性,严格地将宗教和哲学分开,以及一种实体内在本体论的兴起。有人认为,这种“激进”的转变为民主主义带来了哲学基础。根据我接下来要捍卫的论点,内在本体论确实具有政治颠覆的意义。在马基雅维利的文本和思想的启发下,它导致了焦点的根本改变:从神学的等级结构到我们生活的世界的水平结构,在这个世界中,所有人都是平等的。这种激进的变化在公民国家层面产生了影响:例如,思想自由和言论自由的必要性,这可能导致抵抗、拒绝和不服从。我认为,这种斯宾诺莎式的激进主义,只有在我们一方面考虑到他的圈子里其他思想家的激进思想,另一方面考虑到他的反对者所构建的斯宾诺莎的颠覆性形象时,才能得到充分的理解。
{"title":"Radical Enlightenment, Enlightened Subversion, and Spinoza","authors":"S. Lavaert","doi":"10.21825/philosophica.82127","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21825/philosophica.82127","url":null,"abstract":"An important philosophical turn that took place in seventeenthand eighteenth-century Enlightenment thought was the abandonment of transcendence, the strict separation of religion and philosophy, and the rise of a one-substance immanent ontology. It has been argued that this ‘radical’ turn brought about the philosophical foundation for democracy. According to the thesis I will defend in what follows, immanent ontology indeed has a political subversive meaning. Inspired by the texts and ideas of Machiavelli, it entailed a radical change of focus: from a theologicalhierarchical structure to the horizontal structure of the world in which we live and in which all humans are equal. This radical change had consequences at the level of the civil state: e.g., the necessity of free thought and free speech, which may lead to resistance, refusal, and disobedience. I will argue that this Spinozistic radicalism can only be adequately understood if we take into account the radical thought of fellow thinkers from his circle, on the one hand, and the subversive image of Spinoza as constructed by his opponents on the other.","PeriodicalId":36843,"journal":{"name":"Argumenta Philosophica","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2014-01-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"83558038","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
Algebraic symbolism in the first algebraic works in the Iberian Peninsula 伊比利亚半岛最早的代数著作中的代数符号
Q4 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2012-01-02 DOI: 10.21825/philosophica.82141
Fatima ROMERO VALLHONESTA
{"title":"Algebraic symbolism in the first algebraic works in the Iberian Peninsula","authors":"Fatima ROMERO VALLHONESTA","doi":"10.21825/philosophica.82141","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21825/philosophica.82141","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":36843,"journal":{"name":"Argumenta Philosophica","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2012-01-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"86163806","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 3
Algebraic symbolism in medieval Arabic algebra 中世纪阿拉伯代数中的代数符号
Q4 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2012-01-02 DOI: 10.21825/philosophica.82139
J. Oaks
Medieval Arabic books read more or less like transcriptions of lectures, a fact that stems from the fundamentally oral nature of medieval Islamic civilization. Books covering algebra are no exception. There we find algebraic solutions to problems written all out in words, with no notation even for numbers. But problems were not solved rhetorically. Algebraists would work out a problem in some kind of notation on a dust board or other ephemeral surface, and to record it in a book a rhetorical version of the calculations would be composed. From early texts it appears that only the coefficients of polynomials were written in Hindi notation. But in the Maghreb in the twelfth century a notation specific to algebra developed in which the power was indicated also. This symbolic notation is not presented as a scientific development in the manuscripts, but is instead shown in textbooks to instruct students in its use. In this article we explain the notation, its context, and how it differs from modern notation.
中世纪的阿拉伯书读起来或多或少像讲座的抄写本,这一事实源于中世纪伊斯兰文明的口述本质。代数书籍也不例外。在那里,我们发现问题的代数解都是用文字写出来的,甚至没有数字符号。但问题并不是靠修辞来解决的。代数学家会在黑板或其他短暂的表面上用某种符号来解决问题,然后把计算结果写成一种修辞形式记录在书上。从早期的文本来看,似乎只有多项式的系数是用印地语符号写的。但在12世纪的马格里布,一种专门用于代数的符号发展起来,其中也表示了幂。这种符号符号在手稿中并没有作为一种科学发展,而是在教科书中展示,以指导学生使用它。在本文中,我们将解释这种记谱法,它的上下文,以及它与现代记谱法的区别。
{"title":"Algebraic symbolism in medieval Arabic algebra","authors":"J. Oaks","doi":"10.21825/philosophica.82139","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21825/philosophica.82139","url":null,"abstract":"Medieval Arabic books read more or less like transcriptions of lectures, a fact that stems from the fundamentally oral nature of medieval Islamic civilization. Books covering algebra are no exception. There we find algebraic solutions to problems written all out in words, with no notation even for numbers. But problems were not solved rhetorically. Algebraists would work out a problem in some kind of notation on a dust board or other ephemeral surface, and to record it in a book a rhetorical version of the calculations would be composed. From early texts it appears that only the coefficients of polynomials were written in Hindi notation. But in the Maghreb in the twelfth century a notation specific to algebra developed in which the power was indicated also. This symbolic notation is not presented as a scientific development in the manuscripts, but is instead shown in textbooks to instruct students in its use. In this article we explain the notation, its context, and how it differs from modern notation.","PeriodicalId":36843,"journal":{"name":"Argumenta Philosophica","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2012-01-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"83144006","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 9
The problem of Kuhnian rationality 库恩理性的问题
Q4 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2012-01-02 DOI: 10.21825/philosophica.82144
Rogier de Langhe
{"title":"The problem of Kuhnian rationality","authors":"Rogier de Langhe","doi":"10.21825/philosophica.82144","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21825/philosophica.82144","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":36843,"journal":{"name":"Argumenta Philosophica","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2012-01-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"80400120","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The role of symbolic language in the transformation of mathematics 符号语言在数学转化中的作用
Q4 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2012-01-02 DOI: 10.21825/philosophica.82142
Ma Rosa Massa Esteve
{"title":"The role of symbolic language in the transformation of mathematics","authors":"Ma Rosa Massa Esteve","doi":"10.21825/philosophica.82142","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21825/philosophica.82142","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":36843,"journal":{"name":"Argumenta Philosophica","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2012-01-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"73881176","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Surmounting obstacles: circulation and adoption of algebraic symbolism 跨越障碍:代数符号的流通与采用
Q4 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2012-01-02 DOI: 10.21825/philosophica.82138
Albrecht Heeffer
This introductory paper provides an overview of four contributions on the epistemological functions of mathematical symbolism as it emerged in Arabic and European treatises on algebra. The evolution towards symbolic algebra was a long and difficult process in which many obstacles had to be overcome. Three of these obstacles, related to the circulation and adoption of symbolism, are highlighted in this special volume: 1) the transition of material practices of algebraic calculation to discursive practices and text production, 2) the transition from manuscript production to printed works involving material limitations of typefaces, and 3) the transition of algebraic symbolism from a system of notation and representation to a tool of mathematical analysis. This paper will conclude with the observation that the whole development towards symbolization can be considered an obstacle by itself in the sense of ‘epistemic obstacles’ as used by Brousseau.
这篇介绍性的论文概述了数学符号的认识论功能的四个贡献,因为它出现在阿拉伯和欧洲的代数论文中。向符号代数的演变是一个漫长而艰难的过程,必须克服许多障碍。这些障碍中的三个,与符号的流通和采用有关,在这个特别的卷中被强调:1)代数计算的物质实践向话语实践和文本生产的过渡,2)从手稿生产到涉及字体材料限制的印刷作品的过渡,以及3)代数符号从符号和表示系统向数学分析工具的过渡。本文的结论是,按照布鲁梭所使用的“认知障碍”的意义,符号化的整个发展本身可以被视为一个障碍。
{"title":"Surmounting obstacles: circulation and adoption of algebraic symbolism","authors":"Albrecht Heeffer","doi":"10.21825/philosophica.82138","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21825/philosophica.82138","url":null,"abstract":"This introductory paper provides an overview of four contributions on the epistemological functions of mathematical symbolism as it emerged in Arabic and European treatises on algebra. The evolution towards symbolic algebra was a long and difficult process in which many obstacles had to be overcome. Three of these obstacles, related to the circulation and adoption of symbolism, are highlighted in this special volume: 1) the transition of material practices of algebraic calculation to discursive practices and text production, 2) the transition from manuscript production to printed works involving material limitations of typefaces, and 3) the transition of algebraic symbolism from a system of notation and representation to a tool of mathematical analysis. This paper will conclude with the observation that the whole development towards symbolization can be considered an obstacle by itself in the sense of ‘epistemic obstacles’ as used by Brousseau.","PeriodicalId":36843,"journal":{"name":"Argumenta Philosophica","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2012-01-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"76491437","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 4
Printers and algebraists in Mid-16th Century France 16世纪中期法国的印刷工和代数学家
Q4 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2012-01-02 DOI: 10.21825/philosophica.82140
François Loget
In this paper, we investigate the relationships between two algebraists of the mid-sixteenth century France (Jacques Peletier du Mans and Pierre de La Ramee), and their printers, (Guillaume Cavellat, Jean de Tournes and Andre Wechel). Both authors published a treatise on algebra at a time when they were involved in a debate concerning French spelling. Did the consideration of these authors concerning symbolism had something to do with their reflections on vernacular language? In Peletier and Ramus's books, the symbolism is specific. Was their choice with regards to the use of symbolism influenced by their printers, or not?
在本文中,我们研究了16世纪中期法国的两位代数家(Jacques Peletier du Mans和Pierre de La Ramee)和他们的印刷商(Guillaume Cavellat, Jean de Tournes和Andre Wechel)之间的关系。两位作者都发表了一篇关于代数的论文,当时他们正卷入一场关于法语拼写的辩论。这些作者对象征主义的思考是否与他们对本土语言的思考有关?在Peletier和Ramus的书中,象征主义是具体的。他们在使用象征主义方面的选择是否受到印刷商的影响?
{"title":"Printers and algebraists in Mid-16th Century France","authors":"François Loget","doi":"10.21825/philosophica.82140","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21825/philosophica.82140","url":null,"abstract":"In this paper, we investigate the relationships between two algebraists of the mid-sixteenth century France (Jacques Peletier du Mans and Pierre de La Ramee), and their printers, (Guillaume Cavellat, Jean de Tournes and Andre Wechel). Both authors published a treatise on algebra at a time when they were involved in a debate concerning French spelling. Did the consideration of these authors concerning symbolism had something to do with their reflections on vernacular language? In Peletier and Ramus's books, the symbolism is specific. Was their choice with regards to the use of symbolism influenced by their printers, or not?","PeriodicalId":36843,"journal":{"name":"Argumenta Philosophica","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2012-01-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"83395756","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 3
The rationality of scientific reasoning in the context of pursuit: Drawing appropriate distinctions 追求背景下科学推理的合理性:适当的区分
Q4 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2012-01-02 DOI: 10.21825/philosophica.82146
Dunja Šešelja, Laszlo Kosolosky, Christian Straßer
The aim of this paper is to disambiguate between different notions of pursuit worthiness regarding scientific inquiries. To this end we propose a unifying pattern of pursuit worthiness: “It is rational for Y to pursue X if and only if pursuing X is conducive of the set of goals Z.” By showing in which ways variables X, Y, and Z can be changed, we present different notions of pursuit and pursuit worthiness. With respect to variable X, we distinguish the pursuit of scientific theories, epistemic objects, and technological developments. With respect to variable Z, we distinguish between epistemic and practical pursuit worthiness. Finally, with respect to variable Y, we distinguish between individual and communal pursuit worthiness. By means of these distinctions we are able to explicate some of the major ambiguities underlying the concept of pursuit of pursuit worthiness, as well as to shed light on some confusions in philosophical literature that have resulted from their neglect. 52 D. SesELJA, L. KOSOLOSKY & C. STRASSER
本文的目的是消除关于科学探究的追求价值的不同概念之间的歧义。为此,我们提出了一个追求价值的统一模式:“当且仅当追求X有利于目标Z时,Y追求X是合理的。”通过展示变量X、Y和Z可以改变的方式,我们提出了追求和追求价值的不同概念。关于变量X,我们区分了对科学理论、认知对象和技术发展的追求。对于变量Z,我们区分了认知价值和实践追求价值。最后,关于变量Y,我们区分个人追求价值和集体追求价值。通过这些区别,我们能够解释追求追求价值这一概念背后的一些主要模糊之处,同时也能阐明哲学文献中由于忽视这一概念而造成的一些混乱。[52]谢谢嘉,柯索洛斯基,史特拉瑟
{"title":"The rationality of scientific reasoning in the context of pursuit: Drawing appropriate distinctions","authors":"Dunja Šešelja, Laszlo Kosolosky, Christian Straßer","doi":"10.21825/philosophica.82146","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21825/philosophica.82146","url":null,"abstract":"The aim of this paper is to disambiguate between different notions of pursuit worthiness regarding scientific inquiries. To this end we propose a unifying pattern of pursuit worthiness: “It is rational for Y to pursue X if and only if pursuing X is conducive of the set of goals Z.” By showing in which ways variables X, Y, and Z can be changed, we present different notions of pursuit and pursuit worthiness. With respect to variable X, we distinguish the pursuit of scientific theories, epistemic objects, and technological developments. With respect to variable Z, we distinguish between epistemic and practical pursuit worthiness. Finally, with respect to variable Y, we distinguish between individual and communal pursuit worthiness. By means of these distinctions we are able to explicate some of the major ambiguities underlying the concept of pursuit of pursuit worthiness, as well as to shed light on some confusions in philosophical literature that have resulted from their neglect. 52 D. SesELJA, L. KOSOLOSKY & C. STRASSER","PeriodicalId":36843,"journal":{"name":"Argumenta Philosophica","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2012-01-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"77254087","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 38
Fifth part of the definition of knowledge 第五部分知识的定义
Q4 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2012-01-02 DOI: 10.21825/philosophica.82145
A. Grobler
In this paper, I raise a problem for the widely accepted view that knowledge is degettierized justified true belief. The problem is that one can acquire degettierized justified true beliefs even if one is unable to apply those beliefs in practice or use them in the formation of further justified beliefs. Such beliefs, even though degettierized, justified and true, hardly amount to knowledge. So a fifth part of the definition of knowledge is called for. As a solution, I suggest that beliefs count as knowledge only when they are structured in such a way that they can be employed in the process of beliefor knowledge-formation. This required structure can be explicated in terms of Wiśniewski‟s logic of questions. In order for a belief to count as knowledge, I will argue, it is necessary for it to be liable to figure in an erotetic argument. 1 I thank anonymous referees who have suggested a number of amendments.
在本文中,我对被广泛接受的观点提出了一个问题,即知识是被证明是正确的真信念。问题是,一个人可以获得去根化的被证明正确的真信念,即使他不能在实践中应用这些信念或在形成进一步的被证明正确的信念时使用它们。这样的信念,即使是去中心化的、合理的和真实的,也很难算作知识。所以需要知识定义的第五部分。作为一种解决方案,我建议,只有当信念被构建成一种可以在信念知识形成过程中使用的方式时,它们才算知识。这种必要的结构可以用Wiśniewski的问题逻辑来解释。为了使一种信仰算作知识,我将论证,它有必要在情色的论证中表现出来。我感谢那些匿名的推荐人,他们提出了一些修改意见。
{"title":"Fifth part of the definition of knowledge","authors":"A. Grobler","doi":"10.21825/philosophica.82145","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21825/philosophica.82145","url":null,"abstract":"In this paper, I raise a problem for the widely accepted view that knowledge is degettierized justified true belief. The problem is that one can acquire degettierized justified true beliefs even if one is unable to apply those beliefs in practice or use them in the formation of further justified beliefs. Such beliefs, even though degettierized, justified and true, hardly amount to knowledge. So a fifth part of the definition of knowledge is called for. As a solution, I suggest that beliefs count as knowledge only when they are structured in such a way that they can be employed in the process of beliefor knowledge-formation. This required structure can be explicated in terms of Wiśniewski‟s logic of questions. In order for a belief to count as knowledge, I will argue, it is necessary for it to be liable to figure in an erotetic argument. 1 I thank anonymous referees who have suggested a number of amendments.","PeriodicalId":36843,"journal":{"name":"Argumenta Philosophica","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2012-01-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"85934916","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
期刊
Argumenta Philosophica
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1