首页 > 最新文献

Constellations-An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory最新文献

英文 中文
Rethinking hybrid regimes: The American case 重新思考混合体制:美国的案例
IF 0.7 Pub Date : 2023-08-18 DOI: 10.1111/1467-8675.12700
Jean L. Cohen
{"title":"Rethinking hybrid regimes: The American case","authors":"Jean L. Cohen","doi":"10.1111/1467-8675.12700","DOIUrl":"10.1111/1467-8675.12700","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":51578,"journal":{"name":"Constellations-An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.7,"publicationDate":"2023-08-18","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"47190670","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Recognition of struggle: Transcending the oppressive dynamics of desire 对斗争的认识:超越欲望的压迫动力
IF 1.2 Q3 POLITICAL SCIENCE Pub Date : 2023-08-16 DOI: 10.1111/1467-8675.12711
Magnus Hörnqvist
<p>Recognition seems to present us with an unresolvable predicament, whether we are aware of it or not. The predicament can be formulated in the following way. We inescapably strive to be recognized by others, since recognition is a precondition for our existence as social beings in any society, while the very recognition we strive for constrains us and cements an unequal social order. The first part of the predicament, the relentless striving to reach recognition, is the basic insight conveyed by the Hegelian master-and-slave dialectic (Hegel, <span>2018</span>). It has been reiterated many times and was axiomatic in the renaissance of the concept of recognition in the early 1990s, associated with authentic self-realization (Taylor, <span>1992</span>) or the moral call of struggles (Honneth, <span>1992</span>). The oppressive consequences, on the other hand, have been emphasized by theoreticians who were attentive to existing power asymmetries as well as familiar with Hegel's argument. Recognition was inevitably oppressive, conceived of as ideological interpellation (Althusser, <span>2001</span>), objectification of the self (Sartre, <span>2018</span>), a mechanism of subjection (Butler, <span>1997</span>), regressive assertion of victimization (Brown, <span>1995</span>), or as a fundamentally skewed concept (McNay, <span>2008</span>). In this line of thinking, desire for recognition reinforced inequality, instead of realizing more freedom.</p><p>This predicament has shaped the contemporary discussion. One response was trying to find a middle way and reconcile opposing dynamics. Recognition was seen to be inherently ambivalent: crucial for personhood and autonomy, as well as for making people accommodate to stratified social positions (Allen, <span>2021</span>; Ikäheimo et al, <span>2021</span>; McQueen, <span>2014</span>). On the ambivalence reading, recognition was a mix: sometimes beneficial and sometimes detrimental. Recognition was vital for personal growth and well-being, yet oppressive when (and only when) it involved misrecognition by the other, as a consequence of its “determining identification and oppressive ascriptions” (Jaeggi, <span>2021</span>, p. 1; see also Honneth, <span>2018</span>). From this perspective, there is good recognition, which furthers personal development, as opposed to bad recognition, which constrains people. Is thereby the predicament of recognition resolved? It depends on how the oppressive element is conceptualized. Proponents of the ambivalence reading locate the oppressive mechanisms of recognition to identities and ascriptions. What if the impact of power stretches beyond identities and ascriptions? This article looks at desire and its dynamic. The thesis of what might be called the oppressive dynamics of desire, rather than identities or ascriptions, has been chosen as the point of departure. On this line of thinking, desire for recognition is from the very outset shaped by unequal social structures, and
无论我们是否意识到,承认似乎给我们带来了一个无法解决的困境。这种困境可以用以下方式表述。我们不可避免地努力得到他人的认可,因为在任何社会中,认可都是我们作为社会存在的先决条件,而我们努力争取的认可却限制了我们,巩固了一个不平等的社会秩序。困境的第一部分,不懈地努力达到承认,是黑格尔的主仆辩证法所传达的基本见解(Hegel, 2018)。它被重申了很多次,并且在20世纪90年代早期认识概念的复兴中是不言自明的,与真实的自我实现(Taylor, 1992)或斗争的道德召唤(Honneth, 1992)有关。另一方面,关注现有权力不对称并熟悉黑格尔论证的理论家强调了压迫性后果。承认不可避免地是压迫性的,被认为是意识形态的质询(阿尔都塞,2001年)、自我的客观化(萨特,2018年)、一种臣服机制(巴特勒,1997年)、受害的倒退断言(布朗,1995年),或者是一种根本性的扭曲概念(麦克内,2008年)。在这种思路下,渴望得到认可加剧了不平等,而不是实现更多的自由。这种困境塑造了当代的讨论。一种反应是试图找到一条中间道路,调和对立的动态。认可被认为是内在矛盾的:对人格和自主性至关重要,以及使人们适应分层的社会地位(Allen, 2021;Ikäheimo等,2021;麦昆,2014)。从矛盾心理的角度来看,认可是一种混合:有时是有益的,有时是有害的。承认对个人成长和幸福至关重要,但当(且仅当)它涉及到他人的错误认识时,它是压迫性的,因为它“决定性的认同和压迫性的归属”(Jaeggi, 2021, p. 1;另见Honneth, 2018)。从这个角度来看,好的认知会促进个人发展,而不好的认知会限制人们。因此,承认的困境解决了吗?这取决于压迫因素是如何被概念化的。矛盾心理阅读的支持者将认同的压迫机制定位于身份和归属。如果权力的影响超越了身份和归属呢?这篇文章着眼于欲望及其动态。这个命题可以被称为欲望的压迫动力
{"title":"Recognition of struggle: Transcending the oppressive dynamics of desire","authors":"Magnus Hörnqvist","doi":"10.1111/1467-8675.12711","DOIUrl":"10.1111/1467-8675.12711","url":null,"abstract":"&lt;p&gt;Recognition seems to present us with an unresolvable predicament, whether we are aware of it or not. The predicament can be formulated in the following way. We inescapably strive to be recognized by others, since recognition is a precondition for our existence as social beings in any society, while the very recognition we strive for constrains us and cements an unequal social order. The first part of the predicament, the relentless striving to reach recognition, is the basic insight conveyed by the Hegelian master-and-slave dialectic (Hegel, &lt;span&gt;2018&lt;/span&gt;). It has been reiterated many times and was axiomatic in the renaissance of the concept of recognition in the early 1990s, associated with authentic self-realization (Taylor, &lt;span&gt;1992&lt;/span&gt;) or the moral call of struggles (Honneth, &lt;span&gt;1992&lt;/span&gt;). The oppressive consequences, on the other hand, have been emphasized by theoreticians who were attentive to existing power asymmetries as well as familiar with Hegel's argument. Recognition was inevitably oppressive, conceived of as ideological interpellation (Althusser, &lt;span&gt;2001&lt;/span&gt;), objectification of the self (Sartre, &lt;span&gt;2018&lt;/span&gt;), a mechanism of subjection (Butler, &lt;span&gt;1997&lt;/span&gt;), regressive assertion of victimization (Brown, &lt;span&gt;1995&lt;/span&gt;), or as a fundamentally skewed concept (McNay, &lt;span&gt;2008&lt;/span&gt;). In this line of thinking, desire for recognition reinforced inequality, instead of realizing more freedom.&lt;/p&gt;&lt;p&gt;This predicament has shaped the contemporary discussion. One response was trying to find a middle way and reconcile opposing dynamics. Recognition was seen to be inherently ambivalent: crucial for personhood and autonomy, as well as for making people accommodate to stratified social positions (Allen, &lt;span&gt;2021&lt;/span&gt;; Ikäheimo et al, &lt;span&gt;2021&lt;/span&gt;; McQueen, &lt;span&gt;2014&lt;/span&gt;). On the ambivalence reading, recognition was a mix: sometimes beneficial and sometimes detrimental. Recognition was vital for personal growth and well-being, yet oppressive when (and only when) it involved misrecognition by the other, as a consequence of its “determining identification and oppressive ascriptions” (Jaeggi, &lt;span&gt;2021&lt;/span&gt;, p. 1; see also Honneth, &lt;span&gt;2018&lt;/span&gt;). From this perspective, there is good recognition, which furthers personal development, as opposed to bad recognition, which constrains people. Is thereby the predicament of recognition resolved? It depends on how the oppressive element is conceptualized. Proponents of the ambivalence reading locate the oppressive mechanisms of recognition to identities and ascriptions. What if the impact of power stretches beyond identities and ascriptions? This article looks at desire and its dynamic. The thesis of what might be called the oppressive dynamics of desire, rather than identities or ascriptions, has been chosen as the point of departure. On this line of thinking, desire for recognition is from the very outset shaped by unequal social structures, and ","PeriodicalId":51578,"journal":{"name":"Constellations-An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.2,"publicationDate":"2023-08-16","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/1467-8675.12711","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"44296844","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Two types of democratic representation for the two wills of the people 两种形式的民主代表人民的两种意愿
IF 1.2 Q3 POLITICAL SCIENCE Pub Date : 2023-08-16 DOI: 10.1111/1467-8675.12707
Tom Malleson
{"title":"Two types of democratic representation for the two wills of the people","authors":"Tom Malleson","doi":"10.1111/1467-8675.12707","DOIUrl":"10.1111/1467-8675.12707","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":51578,"journal":{"name":"Constellations-An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.2,"publicationDate":"2023-08-16","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"45440420","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Parsing the promise of modernism: Habermas, the avant-garde and the aesthetics of normative order 解析现代主义的承诺:哈贝马斯、先锋派和规范秩序的美学
IF 1.2 Q3 POLITICAL SCIENCE Pub Date : 2023-08-16 DOI: 10.1111/1467-8675.12701
Benedict Coleridge
<p>In a 2018 interview with Jürgen Habermas by the Spanish newspaper <i>El Pais</i>, visiting journalists noted that Habermas’ home, bedecked with modern art, presented “a juxtaposition of Bauhaus modernism and Bavaria's staunch conservatism” (Hermoso, <span>2018</span>). The shelves were lined with the German Romantics and the walls adorned with icons of European aesthetic modernism, cohering with the style of the house itself. In fleeting autobiographical remarks made in the preface to his essays in <i>Naturalism and Religion</i>, Habermas proffers an account of his decorative tastes and the experiences and hopes at which they gesture. He writes of the postwar revelations that disclosed a civilizational rupture after 1945, along with the sense of cultural release brought about by the doors being opened “to Expressionist art, to Kafka, Thomas Mann, and Hermann Hesse, to world literature written in English, to the contemporary philosophy of Sartre and the French left-wing Catholics, to Freud and Marx, as well as to the pragmatism of John Dewey…” (Habermas, <span>2008</span>, p. 19). He continues to describe how “the liberating, revolutionary spirit of Modernism found compelling visual expression in Mondrian's constructivism, in the cool geometric lines of Bauhaus architecture, and in uncompromising industrial design” (Habermas, <span>2008</span>, p. 19). Together, these aesthetic movements espoused what Rembert (<span>2015</span>) calls a determination to develop an artistic practice that conveyed a “new world image” (p. 40). According to Habermas, the “cultural opening” instigated by these aesthetic pursuits “went hand in hand with a political opening,” which primarily took the form of “the political constructions of social contract theory…combined with the pioneering spirit and the emancipatory promise of Modernism” (Habermas, <span>2008</span>, p. 19). In this brief sketch Habermas depicts politics and aesthetics working in tandem to drive emancipatory social renewal; the intellectual constructions necessary for political transformation leaned, he suggests, upon the revolutionary social vision framed by modernism's “cool geometry.” This article further explores this connection with a view to examining the role of modernism as an imaginative resource for the kind of normative integration developed by Habermas in his pursuit of the neo-Kantian “project of modernity”—that is, the project of integrating pluralistic mass societies via postmetaphysical rational presuppositions and the normative principles to which they give rise. In excavating and critiquing the resources that inform Habermas’ normative framework, this article locates an important source of inspiration in 20th century European aesthetic modernism, which, I argue, supplies something like an “orienting background metaphor,” and a methodological resource, for the envisioning of a detranscendentalized normativity based upon the dualism of form and content (Blumenberg, <span>1983</span>,
相反,我们可以重新审视跨文化可行的规范秩序,从具有形式、微小和理性自足特性的形象,转向从伦理意义的材料--历史和社会现实--中提取的 "被形式所取消 "的成分(Schiavone,2012 年,第 39 页)。 然而,"审美的东西 "与它所体现和表达的知识是密不可分的;正如伽达默尔所说,在彻底主观化的条件下,它是无法被接受或 "理解 "的。要 "理解 "审美判断的对象,必须以构成其审美性质的意义为条件;这就需要接近语言的生活,接近在特定生活形式中塑造诸如 "品味 "或 "典范 "等审美价值的语言游戏。因此,我们接近维特根斯坦(1970 年)提出的美学与文化相互依存的论点,即 "我们称之为审美判断表达的词语,在我们所说的一个时期的文化中起着非常复杂但又非常明确的作用。要描述这些词语的使用,或者要描述有教养的品味的含义,就必须描述一种文化"(第 8 页)。因此,"在描述音乐品味时,你必须描述儿童是否举办音乐会,妇女是否举办音乐会,或者男人是否只举办音乐会",以及这些安排背后的价值表述(维特根斯坦,1970 年,第 83 页)。考虑到这种结合,审美判断超越了我们辨别对象并将其与可用概念联系起来的认知过程;它在重要意义上仍然是存在的。审美判断超越了我们通过前概念直觉来优化视角的原始感知能力,它使我们与品味,进而与 "整个文化 "发生联系。因此,审美判断具有我们存在于世界中的现象学条件,在伽达默尔看来,这涉及到一种诠释学情境,每当我们试图理解一种外来的传统或对象时,我们的自我理解就会参与其中。因此,正如伽达默尔(2013)所坚持的,"纯粹的视觉和纯粹的听觉是教条式的抽象,它们人为地缩小了现象。感知总是包含意义"(第 84 页)。这种感知与意义的融合避免了从习惯传承的沉淀中或从有利于 "现代 "叙事自我理解的各种历史经验中提取视觉形式,而是努力承认 "形式在内容中的象征性孕育先于内容在形式下的归属"(梅洛-庞蒂,2012 年,第 304 页)。自主形式、"无世界的感知 "以及 "挤掉真实维度 "的 "单一表面的横向扩散 "等美学理想与内在资源丰富但功能自足的理性理想紧密结合(Taylor, 2014, p.346)。总体而言,它们强化了迈克尔-华纳(Michael Warner)所说的 "自由主义传统中的一种倾向,即把批判理性与不能被赋予内容的东西相提并论,这种批判理性本身不是一种文化形式,而仅仅被视为一种消极的潜能,一种对进一步批判的永久开放性"(Warner, 2004, p.35)。在哈贝马斯对自由主义传统的具体阐述中,它们致力于确保一种道德地形,在此基础上,语言使用者可以在主体间交流的经验中,从意义中分离出规则,从而提供基础性规范,这些规范在其文化不确定性中,在大众社会的价值多元化中具有适当的渺小性。在哈贝马斯(1982 年)看来,这是我们最有可能克服 "激进理性批判 "的工具,因为 "采取'是'或'否'的立场、区分有效与无效的批判能力,被权力与有效性主张的不幸融合所削弱"(第 18 页)。因此,必须有可能设想并阐明一种在认知上具有权威性的社会秩序模式,而不是仅仅依赖于有限的、带有权力色彩的使用中的语言。因此,在哈贝马斯(1992)看来,"理解一个主题性的命题内容的前提是理解相关的言语行为,其意义是在完整的言语行为中'非主题地出现'的"(第 143 页)。哈贝马斯的 "康德主义的主体间延续 "著名地发挥了语言 "作为物种禀赋 "的解释性作用,这种 "物种禀赋 "可以用形式(因而也是普遍的)语法功能来评估(Joas, 2013, p.37)。这也是哈贝马斯 "对康德方法的实用主义消解 "的核心所在,他将基础性预设置于 "我们无法找到功能对等物的实践 "之中,包括将语言本身视为 "物种禀赋",而非使用中的 "自然语言"(Habermas, 2008, p.27)。
{"title":"Parsing the promise of modernism: Habermas, the avant-garde and the aesthetics of normative order","authors":"Benedict Coleridge","doi":"10.1111/1467-8675.12701","DOIUrl":"10.1111/1467-8675.12701","url":null,"abstract":"&lt;p&gt;In a 2018 interview with Jürgen Habermas by the Spanish newspaper &lt;i&gt;El Pais&lt;/i&gt;, visiting journalists noted that Habermas’ home, bedecked with modern art, presented “a juxtaposition of Bauhaus modernism and Bavaria's staunch conservatism” (Hermoso, &lt;span&gt;2018&lt;/span&gt;). The shelves were lined with the German Romantics and the walls adorned with icons of European aesthetic modernism, cohering with the style of the house itself. In fleeting autobiographical remarks made in the preface to his essays in &lt;i&gt;Naturalism and Religion&lt;/i&gt;, Habermas proffers an account of his decorative tastes and the experiences and hopes at which they gesture. He writes of the postwar revelations that disclosed a civilizational rupture after 1945, along with the sense of cultural release brought about by the doors being opened “to Expressionist art, to Kafka, Thomas Mann, and Hermann Hesse, to world literature written in English, to the contemporary philosophy of Sartre and the French left-wing Catholics, to Freud and Marx, as well as to the pragmatism of John Dewey…” (Habermas, &lt;span&gt;2008&lt;/span&gt;, p. 19). He continues to describe how “the liberating, revolutionary spirit of Modernism found compelling visual expression in Mondrian's constructivism, in the cool geometric lines of Bauhaus architecture, and in uncompromising industrial design” (Habermas, &lt;span&gt;2008&lt;/span&gt;, p. 19). Together, these aesthetic movements espoused what Rembert (&lt;span&gt;2015&lt;/span&gt;) calls a determination to develop an artistic practice that conveyed a “new world image” (p. 40). According to Habermas, the “cultural opening” instigated by these aesthetic pursuits “went hand in hand with a political opening,” which primarily took the form of “the political constructions of social contract theory…combined with the pioneering spirit and the emancipatory promise of Modernism” (Habermas, &lt;span&gt;2008&lt;/span&gt;, p. 19). In this brief sketch Habermas depicts politics and aesthetics working in tandem to drive emancipatory social renewal; the intellectual constructions necessary for political transformation leaned, he suggests, upon the revolutionary social vision framed by modernism's “cool geometry.” This article further explores this connection with a view to examining the role of modernism as an imaginative resource for the kind of normative integration developed by Habermas in his pursuit of the neo-Kantian “project of modernity”—that is, the project of integrating pluralistic mass societies via postmetaphysical rational presuppositions and the normative principles to which they give rise. In excavating and critiquing the resources that inform Habermas’ normative framework, this article locates an important source of inspiration in 20th century European aesthetic modernism, which, I argue, supplies something like an “orienting background metaphor,” and a methodological resource, for the envisioning of a detranscendentalized normativity based upon the dualism of form and content (Blumenberg, &lt;span&gt;1983&lt;/span&gt;,","PeriodicalId":51578,"journal":{"name":"Constellations-An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.2,"publicationDate":"2023-08-16","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/1467-8675.12701","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"43760025","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Recognition, power, and trust: Epistemic structural account of ideological recognition 认同、权力与信任:意识形态认同的认知结构解释
IF 1.2 Q3 POLITICAL SCIENCE Pub Date : 2023-08-16 DOI: 10.1111/1467-8675.12708
Hiroki Narita
<p>Recognition is one of the most elusive and ambivalent concepts in political and social thought. In recent studies of the ambivalence of recognition (Ikäheimo et al., <span>2021</span>; Lepold, <span>2019</span>; McQueen, <span>2015</span>), recognition has the emancipatory aspect: Recognition is a necessary condition for individual freedom by forming a social basis of self-worth, and the struggle for recognition plays the significant role in political movements for emancipation. However, recognition has a dominating aspect: The demand for recognition can be exploited as an instrument for domination, reproducing existing problematic practices and identities. For example, sweatshops induce employees to voluntarily subjugate themselves to harsh working conditions by praising the employees’ self-dedicated character and enhancing their self-worth.</p><p>In recent philosophical debates, Axel Honneth has developed the most systematic theory of recognition. He discusses the problem of ambivalence in offering the concept of ideological recognition (Honneth, <span>2007</span>). Honneth's argument consists of two steps. In the first step, he defines ideological recognition as distinct from misrecognition. Misrecognition occurs when addressees believe their subjective self-image is not consistent with the recognition they receive. They feel misrecognized when their self-worth is inflicted. By contrast, the addressees have “good reason to accept” ideological recognition because they attain a stronger sense of self-worth through the recognition (p. 341). However, “ideological forms of recognition suffer a second-level rationality deficit” as it encourages the addressees’ willing subjection to the dominant social order (p. 346). This suggests that ideological recognition, an issue of “second-level rationality,” is judged independently from the addressees’ subjective perspective. Ideological recognition can be defined as that accepted by the addressees from their <i>subjective</i> point of view, but unjustified from an <i>objective</i> or <i>theoretical</i> point of view.</p><p>In the second step, Honneth proposes a substantive standard of ideological recognition, a standard of “how we can draw a distinction between justified and unjustified forms of social recognition” from an objective point of view (p. 340). According to Honneth, recognition is ideological when it maintains the addressees’ self-worth, while the evaluative promise expressed by the recognition cannot be materially instantiated. In the example above, recognizing the self-dedicated employees in the sweatshops is ideological and unjustified, for the sweatshops will not guarantee material and economic conditions for realizing the employees’ dedication to the company (not providing a minimum income level, for instance).</p><p>I argue against Honneth's substantive standard, not the conceptual definition of ideological recognition itself. It is because his standard is not broad enough to capture th
承认是政治和社会思想中最难以捉摸、最矛盾的概念之一。在最近关于认知矛盾心理的研究中(Ikäheimo et al., 2021;Lepold, 2019;McQueen, 2015),承认具有解放的一面:承认是个体自由的必要条件,它形成了自我价值的社会基础,争取承认的斗争在解放的政治运动中起着重要作用。然而,承认有一个主导的方面:对承认的需求可以被利用为统治的工具,再现现有的有问题的做法和身份。例如,血汗工厂通过表扬员工的自我奉献精神,提高员工的自我价值,诱导员工自愿屈服于恶劣的工作条件。在最近的哲学辩论中,Axel Honneth提出了最系统的认知理论。他在提出意识形态认同的概念时讨论了矛盾心理的问题(Honneth, 2007)。Honneth的论证包括两个步骤。在第一步中,他将意识形态识别与错误识别区分开来。当收件人认为他们的主观自我形象与他们得到的认可不一致时,就会发生误认。当他们的自我价值受到伤害时,他们会感到不被认可。相比之下,收件人有“充分的理由接受”意识形态的认可,因为他们通过这种认可获得了更强的自我价值感(第341页)。然而,“意识形态形式的承认遭受第二级理性赤字”,因为它鼓励收件人愿意服从主导的社会秩序(第346页)。这表明,意识形态认同是一个“二级理性”的问题,是独立于收件人的主观视角来判断的。意识形态的承认可以定义为从收件人的主观角度接受,但从客观或理论角度来看是不合理的。
{"title":"Recognition, power, and trust: Epistemic structural account of ideological recognition","authors":"Hiroki Narita","doi":"10.1111/1467-8675.12708","DOIUrl":"10.1111/1467-8675.12708","url":null,"abstract":"&lt;p&gt;Recognition is one of the most elusive and ambivalent concepts in political and social thought. In recent studies of the ambivalence of recognition (Ikäheimo et al., &lt;span&gt;2021&lt;/span&gt;; Lepold, &lt;span&gt;2019&lt;/span&gt;; McQueen, &lt;span&gt;2015&lt;/span&gt;), recognition has the emancipatory aspect: Recognition is a necessary condition for individual freedom by forming a social basis of self-worth, and the struggle for recognition plays the significant role in political movements for emancipation. However, recognition has a dominating aspect: The demand for recognition can be exploited as an instrument for domination, reproducing existing problematic practices and identities. For example, sweatshops induce employees to voluntarily subjugate themselves to harsh working conditions by praising the employees’ self-dedicated character and enhancing their self-worth.&lt;/p&gt;&lt;p&gt;In recent philosophical debates, Axel Honneth has developed the most systematic theory of recognition. He discusses the problem of ambivalence in offering the concept of ideological recognition (Honneth, &lt;span&gt;2007&lt;/span&gt;). Honneth's argument consists of two steps. In the first step, he defines ideological recognition as distinct from misrecognition. Misrecognition occurs when addressees believe their subjective self-image is not consistent with the recognition they receive. They feel misrecognized when their self-worth is inflicted. By contrast, the addressees have “good reason to accept” ideological recognition because they attain a stronger sense of self-worth through the recognition (p. 341). However, “ideological forms of recognition suffer a second-level rationality deficit” as it encourages the addressees’ willing subjection to the dominant social order (p. 346). This suggests that ideological recognition, an issue of “second-level rationality,” is judged independently from the addressees’ subjective perspective. Ideological recognition can be defined as that accepted by the addressees from their &lt;i&gt;subjective&lt;/i&gt; point of view, but unjustified from an &lt;i&gt;objective&lt;/i&gt; or &lt;i&gt;theoretical&lt;/i&gt; point of view.&lt;/p&gt;&lt;p&gt;In the second step, Honneth proposes a substantive standard of ideological recognition, a standard of “how we can draw a distinction between justified and unjustified forms of social recognition” from an objective point of view (p. 340). According to Honneth, recognition is ideological when it maintains the addressees’ self-worth, while the evaluative promise expressed by the recognition cannot be materially instantiated. In the example above, recognizing the self-dedicated employees in the sweatshops is ideological and unjustified, for the sweatshops will not guarantee material and economic conditions for realizing the employees’ dedication to the company (not providing a minimum income level, for instance).&lt;/p&gt;&lt;p&gt;I argue against Honneth's substantive standard, not the conceptual definition of ideological recognition itself. It is because his standard is not broad enough to capture th","PeriodicalId":51578,"journal":{"name":"Constellations-An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.2,"publicationDate":"2023-08-16","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/1467-8675.12708","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"42928382","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Germany's silence: Testimonial injustice in the NSU investigation and willful ignorance in the NSU trial 德国的沉默:NSU调查中的证词不公正和NSU审判中的故意无知
IF 0.7 Pub Date : 2023-08-15 DOI: 10.1111/1467-8675.12703
Hilkje C. Hänel

We can currently see the formation of new nationalist and racist parties or tendencies within established parties to lean towards right-wing politics within many European countries; from the Alternative für Deutschland in Germany, the Partij voor de Vrijheid (PVV) in the Netherlands, Lega Nord or Lega in Italia, Vox in Spain, the Freiheitliche Partei Österreichs, Front National in France, the Sverigedemokraterna in Sweden, Fidesz in Hungary, and Golden Dawn in Greece, to name only a few. At the same time, there has been a surge in racist, fascist, and antisemitic attacks within Europe. Since 1991, Neo-Nazi gangs have attacked migrants and members of antifascist groups, burned down housing facilities for asylum seekers (including facilities for Ukrainian refugees in 2022), disrupted social initiatives, and spread fear (BfV, 2022; cf. Speit, 2021). However, most of these activities were described as the criminal action of socially marginalized individuals, downplaying the organized structure behind these far-right activities and, thus, paving the way for more attacks.1 Part of this paper is to show how the epistemic tools developed by the epistemology of ignorance literature can help to understand (a) why the organized structures of far-right movements are unintelligible within the dominant frame of intelligibility in Europe and (b) how the silence about far-right movements shifts the boundaries for what can be said or done, thus, having deeply problematic repercussions for who can feel safe in Europe. This paper has a modest aim: By bringing into focus contexts of social injustice that have not received much attention in the current literature and by understanding them with the help of existing research from the debate on problematic epistemic practices and philosophy of language, the paper aims to highlight some problematic practices.2

In this paper, I want to concentrate on a series of attacks carried out in Germany. From 2000 to 2007, the National Socialist Underground (NSU) succeeded in murdering 10 people, one police officer, and nine migrants in Germany. The victims are Enver Şimşek, Abdurrahim Özüdoğru, Süleyman Taşköprü, Habil Kılıç, Mehmet Turgut, İsmail Yaşar, Theodoros Boulgarides, Mehmet Kubaşık, Halit Yozgat, and Michèle Kiesewetter. NSU also attempted to murder another 43 times, committed three bomb attacks in Nuremberg and Cologne, as well as 15 robberies. In addition to the three known members of the organization—Beate Zschäpe, Uwe Mundlos, and Uwe Böhnhardt—it remains an open question how many others were involved. However, it can be assumed that they had good connections with at least another 100–200 persons; including confidential informants, members of the German intelligence service and police force, and officials of extreme right-wing parties.3 Yet, instead of investigating even the possibility of a Neo-Nazi terrorist organization as relatives of the victims

在第一种情况下,结构性身份偏见为见证性不公正铺平了道路;在第二种情况下,结构性不公正为主导框架奠定了基础,而主导框架反过来又导致了无知。此外,在第一种情况下,我们可以说这是一个偏见循环,结构性不公正为负面身份偏见提供了基础,而负面身份偏见反过来又为特定的结构性不公正提供了理由或使其合法化。在第二种情况下,我们可以说是一个无知循环,即结构性不公正为主流框架和与之相伴的无知提供了基础,而主流框架和无知反过来又助长和复制了已经存在的结构性不公正。然而,文献中往往没有认识到的是,还有一个进一步的反馈循环,即见证不公正是故意的诠释学无知的一种表现,而诠释学无知反过来又为进一步的无知的延续提供了理由,从而制造出更多的见证不公正案例。在本节中,我认为理解证词不公正与故意诠释学无知之间的反馈循环有助于了解两者是如何促成现有的、有问题的框架的,而这些框架塑造了社会中可以说什么和做什么的面貌。让我们来解读一下反馈回路:证言不公与诠释学不公和无知都有关系,因为我们的认识论资源依赖于所说的内容和吸引我们注意力的内容。例如,我知道代数是因为学校里有人教过我代数,我知道如何操作咖啡机是因为我读过别人写的说明书,我知道关于无知的认识论是因为有人在大学里给了我理解哲学的工具,还有人写了关于无知的认识论供别人阅读。我能知道什么,取决于有什么人或什么东西可以传达这些知识,也取决于我是否愿意倾听。然而,有些东西比其他东西更容易获得,有些人比其他人获得了更多传递知识的空间。因此,进入我们的主流诠释学资源14 的也是一个问题,即谁有资格作证,谁在主流框架内说话,因此是可理解的,谁被授予可信度。一些人获得了可信度,而另一些人则没有,这至少部分是由于我们的主流诠释学资源和我们的可理解性框架的一部分。由于边缘认识论资源能够唤起处于支配地位的认识者对世界某些部分的关注,而这些部分是他们之前没有注意到的,因此这些资源常常被先发制人地视为无足轻重;它们不属于支配性诠释学资源的一部分,因此,对于处于支配地位的认识者来说,它们仍然是不可理解的。这就是为什么边缘化个人的证词得不到或仅得到不充分的采纳,这些个人遭受证词不公正之苦。然而,这些证词不被采纳的事实有助于再现诠释学上的无知现象,即一些经验仍然是处于支配地位的认识者无法理解的。因此,证词不公正塑造了我们社会世界中什么可以说,什么可以被理解的格局。重要的是,波尔豪斯引导我们关注这样一个事实,即诸如见证不公正这样的结构性不公正并非纯粹的结构现象,相反,它们是由个人实施的结构现象。正如米尔斯(2007)所言,认识论上的无知是我们解释世界的认知缺陷,但并非所有因素都是我们无法控制的。相反,解释学上的无知是故意的,因为它是一种否定,即主导知识者拒绝从边缘知识者那里了解资源(参见 Pohlhaus, 2012)。因此,占主导地位的知识者积极地塑造了在见证交流中可以说的话,以及哪些话是听不到或不被承认的。当考虑到占主导地位的知识者所处的社会地位时,这一点尤为重要,因为他们与边缘化个体之间存在着(制度性的)权威关系,同时他们也可以塑造哪些人在诠释学上仍然被边缘化。在此,我们的注意力也应转移到国家科学大学审判的主审法官身上,而不应只关注调查警官。尽管警方调查的缺陷并非主审法官的过错,但他们未能解决这些问题,也未能对调查人员的行为表示歉意,这无疑是雪上加霜。
{"title":"Germany's silence: Testimonial injustice in the NSU investigation and willful ignorance in the NSU trial","authors":"Hilkje C. Hänel","doi":"10.1111/1467-8675.12703","DOIUrl":"10.1111/1467-8675.12703","url":null,"abstract":"<p>We can currently see the formation of new nationalist and racist parties or tendencies within established parties to lean towards right-wing politics within many European countries; from the Alternative für Deutschland in Germany, the Partij voor de Vrijheid (PVV) in the Netherlands, Lega Nord or Lega in Italia, Vox in Spain, the Freiheitliche Partei Österreichs, Front National in France, the Sverigedemokraterna in Sweden, Fidesz in Hungary, and Golden Dawn in Greece, to name only a few. At the same time, there has been a surge in racist, fascist, and antisemitic attacks within Europe. Since 1991, Neo-Nazi gangs have attacked migrants and members of antifascist groups, burned down housing facilities for asylum seekers (including facilities for Ukrainian refugees in 2022), disrupted social initiatives, and spread fear (BfV, <span>2022</span>; cf. Speit, <span>2021</span>). However, most of these activities were described as the criminal action of socially marginalized individuals, downplaying the organized structure behind these far-right activities and, thus, paving the way for more attacks.<sup>1</sup> Part of this paper is to show how the epistemic tools developed by the epistemology of ignorance literature can help to understand (a) why the organized structures of far-right movements are unintelligible within the dominant frame of intelligibility in Europe and (b) how the silence about far-right movements shifts the boundaries for what can be said or done, thus, having deeply problematic repercussions for who can feel safe in Europe. This paper has a modest aim: By bringing into focus contexts of social injustice that have not received much attention in the current literature and by understanding them with the help of existing research from the debate on problematic epistemic practices and philosophy of language, the paper aims to highlight some problematic practices.<sup>2</sup></p><p>In this paper, I want to concentrate on a series of attacks carried out in Germany. From 2000 to 2007, the National Socialist Underground (NSU) succeeded in murdering 10 people, one police officer, and nine migrants in Germany. The victims are Enver Şimşek, Abdurrahim Özüdoğru, Süleyman Taşköprü, Habil Kılıç, Mehmet Turgut, İsmail Yaşar, Theodoros Boulgarides, Mehmet Kubaşık, Halit Yozgat, and Michèle Kiesewetter. NSU also attempted to murder another 43 times, committed three bomb attacks in Nuremberg and Cologne, as well as 15 robberies. In addition to the three known members of the organization—Beate Zschäpe, Uwe Mundlos, and Uwe Böhnhardt—it remains an open question how many others were involved. However, it can be assumed that they had good connections with at least another 100–200 persons; including confidential informants, members of the German intelligence service and police force, and officials of extreme right-wing parties.<sup>3</sup> Yet, instead of investigating even the possibility of a Neo-Nazi terrorist organization as relatives of the victims ","PeriodicalId":51578,"journal":{"name":"Constellations-An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.7,"publicationDate":"2023-08-15","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/1467-8675.12703","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"48041537","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Movement parties of the left, right, and center: A discursive-organizational approach 左翼、右翼和中间派的运动政党:一种话语组织方法
IF 1.2 Q3 POLITICAL SCIENCE Pub Date : 2023-08-15 DOI: 10.1111/1467-8675.12705
Seongcheol Kim
<p>The term “movement party” has gained widespread currency in the social sciences in recent years, finding extensive application to political parties ranging from the radical left (Della Porta et al., <span>2017</span>) to the far right (Caiani & Císař, <span>2019</span>; Pirro & Castelli Gattinara, <span>2018</span>). Unlike with other academic buzzwords such as “populism,” however, there is also a notable lack of readily identifiable and competing theoretical paradigms that have made systematic attempts at conceptualizing the term—a problem that Kitschelt (<span>2006</span>, p. 278) already pointed out with his arguably first such attempt, noting that “movement party” lacks well-defined status as “a formal concept with a specific terminological content.” Since then, an influential strand of scholarship building on Kitschelt's work has emerged around what might be termed an <i>interactive-mobilizational</i> approach, for which the primary definitional criterion for being a “movement party” is a hybridity of mobilizational repertoires in the electoral-institutional and protest arenas giving rise to a loosely formalized interactive balance between movement and party orientations (hence the proposed syntagma “interactive-mobilizational”). As will be argued in the following, while this approach has succeeded in spawning a wide range of applications across distinct party types (from anti-austerity to far-right), the definitional focus on protest activity concedes insufficient attention to the organizational dimension and renders the concept of movement parties more or less reducible to what Borbáth and Hutter (<span>2021</span>) have referred to as “protesting parties.” In recognizing both the merits and limitations of this literature, this paper proposes an alternative <i>discursive-organizational</i> approach, drawing on the author's previous work based on the post-foundational discourse theory of Laclau and Mouffe (<span>2001</span>[1985]) to conceptualize movement parties as a distinct form of political organization: one that is predicated on horizontal integration of autonomously organized movement actors as the basic decision-making agents and constituent subjects within the party. From this perspective, I go on to examine three examples of movement parties of the radical left, center, and far right, respectively: the CUP (<i>Candidatures</i> <i>d'Unitat</i> <i>Popular</i>) in Catalonia, the (now defunct) Együtt in Hungary, and the Right Sector in Ukraine. All three examples vividly illustrate the inherent organizational precarity (and, in some instances, ephemerality) of the movement party form, but also the willingness of these actors to maintain a movement party structure in high-stakes institutional contexts and their ability to exert recognizable political weight within these settings.</p><p>The discursive-organizational approach presented here draws on an expanded framework of post-foundational discourse theory in which political
虽然有关右翼地带在这一阶段内部组织的详细资料并不容易获得,但可以在此发现某种运动党的逻辑,即在政治委员会层面上集体代表的组织上各不相同的运动之间的横向协调,尽管这与亚罗什的主导作用以及他的表演性自我展示形成了紧张关系,亚罗什作为一名军事指挥官,掌握着随时可以作战的部队,为了 "民族革命 "事业而随意部署这些部队,并将其作为向后马伊丹当局施加政治压力的一种手段。事实上,右翼地带作为一个政党的最初阶段(2014-15 年)的特点是,亚罗什一再威胁,如果某些要求得不到满足,他就会部署武装力量对抗政府--包括类似最后通牒的威胁,即 "全副武装 "向基辅进军,禁止内政部改革和释放被拘留的战士、右翼地带 "还威胁要破坏 2015 年在基辅举行的 "女同性恋、男同性恋、双性恋和变性者骄傲游行"(LGBT Pride March),并最终与警方发生了流血冲突。右翼地带作为极右运动党派的突出作用相对短暂,2015 年后,它在极右武装中的相对份量有所下降,取而代之的是 "国家军团"(与 "亚速营 "有关联)或 S14 等组织。亚罗什本人在穆卡切沃与政府军的武装对峙以及在顿涅茨克机场战役中受伤,使人们对他作为党的领导人的生存能力产生了质疑,因此他在 2015 年底辞职并离开了右翼地带。亚罗什的离任标志着右翼地带第一阶段的结束,在这一阶段,右翼地带将自己视为独立广场 "民族革命 "斗争的延伸,并凭借其武装力量和媒体影响力,从体制外施加了一定的政治影响力--亚罗什作为领导者,具有自上而下的指挥能力(因此也具有讹诈能力),这限制了该党作为极右翼运动参与者的横向协调工具的实际运作程度。但与此同时,亚罗什的影响力本身就取决于右翼地带的联合性质及其背后的运动政党逻辑(无论在实践中有多大局限),它是多个 "民族革命 "团体的集合体,也是作为右翼地带创始逻辑的 "独立广场 "武装联盟的延续。虽然亚罗什能够将自己的形象塑造为独立广场联盟的代表,这使右翼地带持续受到关注,但该党从未在选举中取得过多大的影响力,在2014年5月的总统选举中,亚罗什的得票率不到1%,虽然他在同年10月的议会选举中以微弱优势赢得了一个单议员区席位,但右翼地带本身在全国名单投票中的得票率不到2%。在沃洛德梅尔-泽连斯基(Volodymyr Zelensky)及其政党 "人民公仆"(Servant of the People)获得压倒性胜利的 2019 年总统和议会选举中,右翼地带与其他几个极右翼组织一起支持了 "左翼"(Svoboda)总统候选人和议会名单,但这些候选人在两次选举中的得票率都只有 2%,而且没有议会席位。据悉,右翼地带目前正与自己的部队在持续的乌克兰侵略战争中与俄罗斯侵略军作战,但即使在俄罗斯的国家宣传中,右翼地带也不再是媒体关注的高调目标(例如,与 "亚速军团 "不同),这表明自 2014 年以来,人们对其相关性的看法以及相应的行为体组合发生了很大变化。本文提出了一种研究和概念化 "运动党 "的独创性话语-组织方法,首先讨论了我所称的互动-动员方法中理解的这一概念。话语-组织方法的目的不仅在于忠实于对运动党派的动态理解,即运动党派是内在不稳定的建构,受制于内部张力,往往构成短暂的现象--基切尔特(2006 年)在其关于这一概念的奠基性工作中已经认识到这一点--同时有助于更清晰地理解组织维度,这一维度已被纳入互动-动员文献,但在很大程度上作为一系列可能的选择而未被确定。
{"title":"Movement parties of the left, right, and center: A discursive-organizational approach","authors":"Seongcheol Kim","doi":"10.1111/1467-8675.12705","DOIUrl":"10.1111/1467-8675.12705","url":null,"abstract":"&lt;p&gt;The term “movement party” has gained widespread currency in the social sciences in recent years, finding extensive application to political parties ranging from the radical left (Della Porta et al., &lt;span&gt;2017&lt;/span&gt;) to the far right (Caiani &amp; Císař, &lt;span&gt;2019&lt;/span&gt;; Pirro &amp; Castelli Gattinara, &lt;span&gt;2018&lt;/span&gt;). Unlike with other academic buzzwords such as “populism,” however, there is also a notable lack of readily identifiable and competing theoretical paradigms that have made systematic attempts at conceptualizing the term—a problem that Kitschelt (&lt;span&gt;2006&lt;/span&gt;, p. 278) already pointed out with his arguably first such attempt, noting that “movement party” lacks well-defined status as “a formal concept with a specific terminological content.” Since then, an influential strand of scholarship building on Kitschelt's work has emerged around what might be termed an &lt;i&gt;interactive-mobilizational&lt;/i&gt; approach, for which the primary definitional criterion for being a “movement party” is a hybridity of mobilizational repertoires in the electoral-institutional and protest arenas giving rise to a loosely formalized interactive balance between movement and party orientations (hence the proposed syntagma “interactive-mobilizational”). As will be argued in the following, while this approach has succeeded in spawning a wide range of applications across distinct party types (from anti-austerity to far-right), the definitional focus on protest activity concedes insufficient attention to the organizational dimension and renders the concept of movement parties more or less reducible to what Borbáth and Hutter (&lt;span&gt;2021&lt;/span&gt;) have referred to as “protesting parties.” In recognizing both the merits and limitations of this literature, this paper proposes an alternative &lt;i&gt;discursive-organizational&lt;/i&gt; approach, drawing on the author's previous work based on the post-foundational discourse theory of Laclau and Mouffe (&lt;span&gt;2001&lt;/span&gt;[1985]) to conceptualize movement parties as a distinct form of political organization: one that is predicated on horizontal integration of autonomously organized movement actors as the basic decision-making agents and constituent subjects within the party. From this perspective, I go on to examine three examples of movement parties of the radical left, center, and far right, respectively: the CUP (&lt;i&gt;Candidatures&lt;/i&gt; &lt;i&gt;d'Unitat&lt;/i&gt; &lt;i&gt;Popular&lt;/i&gt;) in Catalonia, the (now defunct) Együtt in Hungary, and the Right Sector in Ukraine. All three examples vividly illustrate the inherent organizational precarity (and, in some instances, ephemerality) of the movement party form, but also the willingness of these actors to maintain a movement party structure in high-stakes institutional contexts and their ability to exert recognizable political weight within these settings.&lt;/p&gt;&lt;p&gt;The discursive-organizational approach presented here draws on an expanded framework of post-foundational discourse theory in which political","PeriodicalId":51578,"journal":{"name":"Constellations-An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.2,"publicationDate":"2023-08-15","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/1467-8675.12705","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"42141960","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
From Jacobin flaws to transformative populism: Left populism and the legacy of European social democracy 从雅各宾的缺陷到变革性民粹主义:左翼民粹主义与欧洲社会民主的遗产
IF 0.7 Pub Date : 2023-06-30 DOI: 10.1111/1467-8675.12698
Kolja Möller

In the established landscape of research in the social sciences, populism is seen as a type of politics that chiefly revolves around the distinction between the “people” and the “elite”.1 Within this, different forms of populism can be distinguished—ranging from right-wing and authoritarian to liberal-centrist and religious varieties. In the camp of the political left, populism is often cast as essentially a democratic endeavor. Drawing on a conception of inclusive peoplehood, which is not opposed to other vulnerable social groups “below” but solely to the “elite above”, many authors emphasize that it is crucial to pursue a populist strategy in order to overcome existing hegemonies, democratic deficits, ossifications, and class-rule (Grattan, 2016; Howse, 2019; Kempf, 2020; McCormick, 2001; Mouffe, 2018). Throughout the past few decades, the landscape of research on left populism has grown considerably. Various studies have investigated the history of anti-establishment popular movements of the 19th century, such as the Narodniki in Russia or the American Populist Party (Canovan, 1981; Kazin, 1995). Further, research has also looked at how, from the 1990s, anti-neoliberal alliances in Latin America had their momentum, entered governmental office, and established a far-reaching renewal of constitutional orders (Linera, 2014; Weyland, 2013). And in particular, in the last decade, the rejuvenation of left politics in Europe and the United States has often relied on populist approaches (Katsambekis & Kioupkiolis, 2019).

Taking a more systematic stance, theories of radical democracy have sought to demonstrate that politics in modern societies is structured around the embodiment of the “people” as an empty signifier. From this perspective, it is not by accident that left varieties of populism can be recurrently observed; their persistence reflects that politics is, at its heart, not only concerned with policy-issues but with “constructing the people” (Laclau, 2014). Thus, populism may not be episodic, accidental, or a specific ideology that brings the vital interests of ordinary people to the fore. Rather, it must be seen as a generalizable discursive strategy—in the words of Ernesto Laclau: the “royal road”—when it comes to the strive for political power (Laclau, 2005, p. 67).2 In recent years, a neo-Machiavellian strand of research has emerged that is not so much concerned with the discursive construction of peoplehood, instead focusing on the materiality of social power. Drawing inspiration from the political philosophy of Early Modernity and Niccolò Machiavelli's insights on the exercise of political rule, these approaches assume that societies are constantly split between the “plebian” people and the ruling elites (McCormick, 2001; Vergara,

在社会科学研究的既定景观中,民粹主义被视为一种主要围绕“人民”和“精英”之间的区别展开的政治类型在这种情况下,不同形式的民粹主义可以被区分开来——从右翼和威权主义到自由中间派和宗教变种。在政治左翼阵营中,民粹主义通常被描绘成本质上是一种民主努力。许多作者借鉴包容性民族的概念,即不反对“下面”的其他弱势社会群体,而只反对“上面的精英”,强调追求民粹主义战略对于克服现有的霸权、民主赤字、僵化和阶级统治至关重要(Grattan, 2016;Howse, 2019;Kempf, 2020;麦考密克,2001;Mouffe, 2018)。在过去的几十年里,对左翼民粹主义的研究有了很大的发展。各种研究调查了19世纪反建制的民众运动的历史,如俄罗斯的民粹党或美国的民粹主义党(Canovan, 1981;金,1995)。此外,研究还着眼于从20世纪90年代开始,拉丁美洲的反新自由主义联盟如何获得动力,进入政府办公室,并建立了深远的宪法秩序更新(Linera, 2014;Weyland, 2013)。特别是,在过去十年中,欧洲和美国左翼政治的复兴往往依赖于民粹主义方法(Katsambekis &Kioupkiolis, 2019)。激进民主理论采取更系统的立场,试图证明现代社会的政治是围绕“人民”作为一个空洞的能指的体现而构建的。从这个角度来看,左翼民粹主义的变种可以反复出现并非偶然;他们的坚持反映了政治的核心不仅是政策问题,而且是“建设人民”(Laclau, 2014)。因此,民粹主义可能不是偶然的、偶然的,也不是把普通民众的切身利益放在首位的特定意识形态。相反,当涉及到政治权力的争夺时,它必须被视为一种概括的话语策略——用埃内斯托·拉克劳的话来说:“皇家之路”(拉克劳,2005,第67页)近年来,一种新马基雅维利式的研究流派出现了,它不太关注民族性的话语建构,而是关注社会权力的物质性。从早期现代性的政治哲学和Niccolò马基雅维利关于政治统治的见解中汲取灵感,这些方法假设社会在“平民”人民和统治精英之间不断分裂(麦考密克,2001;范盖拉,2020)。在这种背景下,民粹主义相当于一种平民政治,“源于对系统性腐败和大众贫困的财富不平等的政治化,试图在统治精英和大众之间平衡社会和政治权力的规模”(Vergara, 2020a,第238页)。然而,左翼民粹主义的历史资产负债表仍然是矛盾的。虽然可以观察到通过动员人民反对精英来改变社会的反复尝试,但它们往往暴露出弄巧成的动力:3一旦民粹主义掌权,就会崩溃为威权政府,无法通过坚持过于简单的人民/精英二元区分来解释复杂的现代社会实际运作方式;除了强调民众动员发挥了关键作用(成功时)或被稀释(不成功时)之外,越来越无法找出政治失败和成功的原因。然而,在当前关于左民粹主义的辩论中,更广泛的反民粹主义批评阵营主要从规范角度提出反对意见(Arato, 2016;科恩,2019;Urbinati, 2019;穆勒,2014)。有人认为,民粹主义形式的政治原则上与自由民主的核心成就不相容,如多元化、三权分立或议会代表制。它们似乎不可避免地与威权政治纠缠在一起,因此需要将其作为一种政治行动加以拒绝。本文旨在通过转移研究领域来超越对左翼民粹主义的评价和拒绝之间的僵化划分:它不是调查民粹主义与政治本身的关系,也不是评估民粹主义是否与自由民主原则相容,而是在“漫长的19世纪”(霍布斯鲍姆)的欧洲社会民主主义的广泛构想阵营中进行讨论的重建。因此,它关注的是这一政治潮流的主要知识分子如何反思以民意为中心的政治的实践潜力和局限性。 正如当代研究民粹主义的话语理论方法所强调的那样,现代社会的政治在很大程度上围绕着人民的角色和围绕其表达的冲突因此,可以识别出广泛的以人民为中心的政治——大众的、民粹的或民间的。这篇文章虽然呼应了民粹主义的定义,即反对精英的以人民为中心的政治,但也强调了民粹主义的必然性和局限性。它审视了民粹主义的内在陷阱,以及它如何应对特定社会秩序结构固有的矛盾和问题。因此,这篇文章的目的是避开一种超历史本身的观点,并对各自的社会环境进行更仔细的检查。本书的目标不是对社会民主主义的整个理论景观进行全面的研究,而是寻找一些主要知识分子是如何根据政治斗争的实践经验来解决以人民为中心的政治问题的。我们认为,我们可以确定一条智力轨迹,它处理的问题是,一个以民意为中心的政治,而不是以精英为中心的政治,是否能够推动社会转型和集体学习过程,或者相反,阻碍它们。诚然,人们不应忽视,19世纪的社会民主主义群众政党与当代无组织的政党格局之间存在着严重差异。然而,本文鼓励进行一项调查,克服左派民粹主义和其他进步政治变体(如社会运动政治)的并列性。Cohen, 2021)或阶级政治(Seferiades, 2019)。根据历史学家克里斯蒂娜·莫里纳(Christina Morina)最近的工作,欧洲社会民主主义被理解为从19世纪中期延伸到第一次世界大战的更广泛的社会运动(莫里纳,2022)它的特点是出现了新的政治组织形式,最显著的是工会和社会民主群众政党。尽管存在严重的内部冲突,但从马克思(Karl Marx)和恩格斯(Friedrich Engels)的著作中得出的对历史和社会的共同看法推动了这一进程。欧洲社会民主主义的决定性特征在于其特有的社会探究模式。正如森里那所强调的,活动人士和知识分子可能围绕一系列问题展开了争论。然而,他们都假设现代社会参与了历史演变的过程,并且一种健全的政治行动必须从一种全面的调查中衍生出来,这种调查澄清了特定历史时刻社会变革的范围。构成运动内部一致性的共同点是假设社会经历了一个历史发展(通常被描述为“阶段”),一个站得住脚的政治行动概念必须对这个过程中固有的客观问题和矛盾作出反应。根据森里纳的说法,“吸引力主要不在于模糊暗示的乌托邦前景,而在于具体要求的与当前相关的科学。”他们(欧洲社会民主党的主要知识分子和积极分子)从马克思的著作中主要汲取了一种面向此时此地的知识承诺,而不是一种只面向明天的未来信念。对他们来说,马克思主义实际上是对现实世界的一种从未完成的研究[…]”(Morina, 2017,第16页)。这是欧洲社会民主主义的统一线索,从马克思和恩格斯的著作传播到非常不同的活动家和知识分子,如爱德华·伯恩斯坦、卡尔·考茨基、弗拉基米尔·伊里奇·列宁和罗莎·卢森堡。需要注意的是,第二国际是一个广泛的政治运动。同样重要的是,工团主义和无政府主义思想在许多国家盛行,马克思和恩格斯的理论并不是19世纪末唯一可用的知识资源然而,如果要重建最终在欧洲劳工运动中创造出特有争议的整体心态,“马克思主义的发明”(森那)发挥了至关重要的作用。本文重构了这场政治运动是如何处理民粹主义方法的潜力和缺点的:第二节表明,19世纪40年代和50年代年轻的马克思和恩格斯最初对以人民为中心的政治持怀疑态度。他们与当时的起义运动争吵不休,发现了雅各宾派的缺陷,这些缺陷往往会给实现社会转型造成相当大的障碍。与第三节所展示的这种批判相反,从19世纪70年代开始,欧洲社会民主主义无论是其改革派还是其更激进的分支都重新动员了民意。 然而,在许多情况下,他们最终失败了,不是由于意志薄弱,而是由于社会进化
{"title":"From Jacobin flaws to transformative populism: Left populism and the legacy of European social democracy","authors":"Kolja Möller","doi":"10.1111/1467-8675.12698","DOIUrl":"10.1111/1467-8675.12698","url":null,"abstract":"<p>In the established landscape of research in the social sciences, populism is seen as a type of politics that chiefly revolves around the distinction between the “people” and the “elite”.<sup>1</sup> Within this, different forms of populism can be distinguished—ranging from right-wing and authoritarian to liberal-centrist and religious varieties. In the camp of the political left, populism is often cast as essentially a democratic endeavor. Drawing on a conception of inclusive peoplehood, which is not opposed to other vulnerable social groups “below” but solely to the “elite above”, many authors emphasize that it is crucial to pursue a populist strategy in order to overcome existing hegemonies, democratic deficits, ossifications, and class-rule (Grattan, <span>2016</span>; Howse, <span>2019</span>; Kempf, <span>2020</span>; McCormick, <span>2001</span>; Mouffe, <span>2018</span>). Throughout the past few decades, the landscape of research on left populism has grown considerably. Various studies have investigated the history of anti-establishment popular movements of the 19th century, such as the Narodniki in Russia or the American Populist Party (Canovan, <span>1981</span>; Kazin, <span>1995</span>). Further, research has also looked at how, from the 1990s, anti-neoliberal alliances in Latin America had their momentum, entered governmental office, and established a far-reaching renewal of constitutional orders (Linera, <span>2014</span>; Weyland, <span>2013</span>). And in particular, in the last decade, the rejuvenation of left politics in Europe and the United States has often relied on populist approaches (Katsambekis &amp; Kioupkiolis, <span>2019</span>).</p><p>Taking a more systematic stance, theories of radical democracy have sought to demonstrate that politics in modern societies is structured around the embodiment of the “people” as an empty signifier. From this perspective, it is not by accident that left varieties of populism can be recurrently observed; their persistence reflects that politics is, at its heart, not only concerned with policy-issues but with “constructing the people” (Laclau, <span>2014</span>). Thus, populism may not be episodic, accidental, or a specific ideology that brings the vital interests of ordinary people to the fore. Rather, it must be seen as a generalizable discursive strategy—in the words of Ernesto Laclau: the “royal road”—when it comes to the strive for political power (Laclau, <span>2005</span>, p. 67).<sup>2</sup> In recent years, a neo-Machiavellian strand of research has emerged that is not so much concerned with the discursive construction of peoplehood, instead focusing on the materiality of social power. Drawing inspiration from the political philosophy of Early Modernity and Niccolò Machiavelli's insights on the exercise of political rule, these approaches assume that societies are constantly split between the “plebian” people and the ruling elites (McCormick, <span>2001</span>; Vergara, <span>","PeriodicalId":51578,"journal":{"name":"Constellations-An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.7,"publicationDate":"2023-06-30","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/1467-8675.12698","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"48989561","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
For Those Who Will Follow; Earth Marred and Renewing Relationships 为那些将追随的人;地球Marred和更新关系
IF 0.7 Pub Date : 2023-06-10 DOI: 10.1111/1467-8675.12679
Yann Allard-Tremblay

Wherever one is in North America, one is on Indigenous lands. Some Indigenous peoples may have been exterminated or removed to other locations, and their contemporary presence may not be highly visible, yet this remains Indigenous land. Nevertheless, rarely do non-Indigenous individuals and institutions consider the responsibilities that come with the fact of being on Indigenous lands (cf. Asch, 2014). To a large extent, this is because settlers regard the state they control as holding a legitimate claim to sovereign authority. Not only is this a claim that bars rightful relationships with Indigenous peoples, it also discloses contemporary settler societies’ disconnection from their Earthboundedness (Asch et al., 2018; Borrows, 2018) because it extends both over peoples and lands.

I propose to consider how, from the locality of some settler states such as Canada and the United States, an intimate connection between the settlers’ claim to sovereignty, mastery and possession, and Modernity/Coloniality, is disclosed, which is significant for understanding the Anthropocene and for envisioning ways of acting otherwise that may help to remedy it. My claims regarding the Anthropocene and Modernity/Coloniality are thus perspectival; they do not pretend to offer complete and universal accounts of either, but rather hope to diagnose distinctive features of both, as experienced and disclosed from the underside of Modernity.

I see the Anthropocene, or the Age of Man, as a symptom of contemporary settler societies’ view of themselves as floating free from the land, to use Brian Burkhart's formulation (2019) and of their associated idea of Man. Man, in this context, does not refer to humanity as a whole, but rather to the Western white cis-gendered heteropatriarchal agent of Modernity/Coloniality (Mignolo, 2007, 2011; Yusoff, 2018) who is driven by a will to mastery and possession (Schulz, 2017; Singh, 2018). This Modern/Colonial Man presents himself as the universal subject, and thereby erases and disqualifies alternative ways of being human (Singh, 2018, Chapter Introduction).

I engage with First Nation and Native American—hereafter Indigenous—political thought and movements to articulate an alternative to the un-earthbound political practices and associated subjectivity of the Man of the Anthropocene. I use Indigenous as a collective shorthand, but my focus is on the distinct political experiences, struggles, and traditions of some of the Indigenous peoples of the lands now claimed by Canada and the United States and the radical alternatives they disclose to dominant Modern/Colonial lifeways, the significance of which extends far beyond their respective contexts. Although I appeal to the distinction between Indigenous and Western thoughts, this is not to essentialize or deny the complexities of either, but in refer

在北美的任何地方,都是在原住民的土地上。一些土著民族可能已经灭绝或迁移到其他地方,他们的当代存在可能不太明显,但这仍然是土著土地。然而,非土著个人和机构很少考虑到居住在土著土地上的责任(参见Asch, 2014)。在很大程度上,这是因为定居者认为他们控制的国家拥有合法的主权权力。这一主张不仅阻碍了与土著人民的合法关系,还揭示了当代定居者社会与他们的地球性的脱节(Asch等人,2018;Borrows, 2018),因为它延伸到人民和土地。我建议考虑如何从加拿大和美国等一些移民国家的地方出发,揭示定居者对主权、掌握和占有的要求与现代性/殖民性之间的密切联系,这对于理解人类世和设想可能有助于补救它的其他行动方式具有重要意义。因此,我关于人类世和现代性/殖民化的主张是前瞻性的;他们并不假装对两者中的任何一个提供完整和普遍的描述,而是希望诊断出两者的独特特征,正如从现代性的背后所经历和揭示的那样。借用布莱恩·伯克哈特(Brian Burkhart)的表述(2019年)和他们对人类的相关概念,我认为人类世或人类时代是当代定居者社会认为自己游离于土地之外的一种症状。在这种背景下,人并不是指整个人类,而是指现代性/殖民性的西方白人顺性别异族父权制代理人(Mignolo, 2007, 2011;Yusoff, 2018),他被一种掌握和占有的意志所驱使(Schulz, 2017;辛格,2018)。这个现代/殖民时代的人将自己呈现为普遍的主体,从而抹去和取消了作为人类的其他方式(Singh, 2018, Chapter Introduction)。我参与了第一民族和印第安人(以下简称土著)的政治思想和运动,以阐明非地球政治实践和人类世的相关主体性的另一种选择。我使用土著作为一个集体的缩写,但我的重点是独特的政治经历,斗争,和一些土著人民的传统,他们现在被加拿大和美国声称拥有主权,以及他们对占主导地位的现代/殖民生活方式的激进选择,其意义远远超出了他们各自的背景。虽然我呼吁区分土著思想和西方思想,但这并不是要本质化或否认两者的复杂性,而是要参考欧洲中心主义对土著生活方式多样性的抹除和贫困的动态影响。在我的观点中,土著思想提供了一条道路,这条道路已经陷入贫困,但可以重建(米尼奥洛&Walsh, 2018),更新彼此之间的关系和责任,以及对其他创造物的责任,并偏离我们物种目前所遵循的生态破坏之路,这已经破坏了地球。我首先解释人类世如何与现代/殖民人类联系起来。然后,我认为,像加拿大这样的移民国家所宣称的完美主权,表达了——并巩固了——人类对主宰和占有世界的自命。我考虑土著人民如何质疑定居者主权的合法性和有效性,以及相反,一些人如何阐明主人和客人之间管理和款待的其他政治关系。这些政治选择可以使政治关系非殖民化和本土化,办法是不断完善定居者的主权,超越掌握和占有,有利于产生于具体生态环境和在具体生态环境内的互惠关系和责任。我认为土地归还运动是一个超越现代性/殖民性的实践项目,通过政治实践和主体性的转变,这有助于人与人之间以及与土地之间的互惠关系的更新。因此,本文对人类世进行了本土化的理论分析,并提出了一条具体的途径来更新与土地的关系,以满足土著人民夺回土地的要求和动员。虽然这篇文章与启蒙辩证法在理性和自然掌握方面的基本论点是一致的,但所采用的方法是不同的。例如,霍克海默和阿多诺通过《奥德赛》揭示了西方传统中启蒙运动与国家社会主义的深刻纠缠,从而阐明了现在(霍克海默和阿多诺)。阿多诺,2002,第218页)。 就我而言,我将土著政治传统视为知识和见解的关键和变革来源,这些知识和见解已被现代性/殖民主义沉默和否认。我把这种方法称为破坏性保守主义,因为它挑战了占主导地位的知识形式和术语,同时复兴和重新进入传统的生活方式。它试图以自己的声音参与土著思想和实践(Allard-Tremblay, 2019),不是为了维护传统,而是以可能支持土著自决、自由与所有人和谐的方式,对目前占主导地位的实践的分离替代方案进行批判性反思。虽然它认为土著传统拥有解决当代问题所需的智力资源,而不必得到西方的帮助或沦为西方的声音,但它并不排除与其他(非殖民化)观点的接触和合作。大约20年前,人类世的概念首次在“地球和环境科学”中获得了基础(Randazzo &Richter, 2021,第2页),但今天关于这个主题的文献已经多样化和增加了多重。这种成果使得熟悉文献的学者,如史蒂夫·门茨(Steve Mentz)认识到,“读者和学者可能会对这种多样性的话语持某种困惑或困惑的态度”(2019年,第1页),特别是如果他们期望对人类世有一个统一的描述。作为回应,Mentz (2019, pp. 1-13)建议人类世应该多元化。因此,我提供了一个关于人类世的解释和解释,不应该被认为是单一的和最终的,特别是考虑到对人类世在否定土著生活方式中所起作用的概念的挑战(Taylor, 2021)。话虽如此,人类世仍然与我们物种所面临的深刻变化的生态环境有关,这些环境与人类行为有关,并引发了共同的(尽管有区别的)政治责任,即使这些环境具有不同的分布原因和后果(夏普,2020)。因此,我承认人类正走向生态毁灭的道路,我认识到有必要个别地,特别是集体地采取行动,防止生态系统的崩溃。然而,我也认识到有必要将人类社会视为嵌入更广泛的自然背景(Henderson, 2000;拉,2003)。这种自然嵌入性告诉我们人类能动性应该如何概念化;具体来说,人类社会与其他受造物之间的关系需要承担责任(Asch等人,2018;Sioui, 1992, p. 9)。在这个意义上,我采用了关于人类世的“非连续性描述”观点的元素,认为它是“与全新世的彻底决裂”,具有“潜在的致命”后果,需要人类采取补救行动(Randazzo &Richter, 2021,第4-5页)。然而,我也采用了“连续本体论”观点的元素,根据这种观点,人类世提供了“一个理论机会,可以采用更广泛、更复杂的理解,来理解构成人类生活及其环境的塑造力量,这种力量必然交织在一起,并不主要存在于人类理性中”(兰达佐& &;Richter, 2021,第5-6页)。然而,值得注意的是,我拒绝与最后一种观点相关的立场,根据这种观点,认识到我们在自然环境中的嵌入性会削弱人类代理的重要性,人类世的意义不是“推迟灾难,而是忍受灾难,并在我们这样做的时候建立解决不公正问题的结构”(Mentz, 2019,第10页)。相反,与Elisa Randazzo和Hannah Richter讨论的土著观点相似,我仍然“毫无疑问地坚持认为,有指导的人类代理是可能的”(2021年,第11页)。事实上,虽然土著的世界观往往认识到生态系统的不稳定平衡,但他们也主张采取负责任的行动来维持这种平衡的重要性,正是通过思考人类与自然环境的关系;正如詹姆斯·塔利所报道的那样,海达人“有一个咒语来提醒自己所有生命系统固有的临界点特征。他们说,‘世界像刀刃一样锋利’”(2018年,第100页)。因此,我们需要采取负责任的行动,避免掉下刀尖,而不仅仅是学会忍受掉下的生活。此外,尽管我承认人类正走在生态毁灭的道路上,但我认识到,产生人类世的实践
{"title":"For Those Who Will Follow; Earth Marred and Renewing Relationships","authors":"Yann Allard-Tremblay","doi":"10.1111/1467-8675.12679","DOIUrl":"10.1111/1467-8675.12679","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Wherever one is in North America, one is on Indigenous lands. Some Indigenous peoples may have been exterminated or removed to other locations, and their contemporary presence may not be highly visible, yet this remains Indigenous land. Nevertheless, rarely do non-Indigenous individuals and institutions consider the responsibilities that come with the fact of being on Indigenous lands (cf. Asch, <span>2014</span>). To a large extent, this is because settlers regard the state they control as holding a legitimate claim to sovereign authority. Not only is this a claim that bars rightful relationships with Indigenous peoples, it also discloses contemporary settler societies’ disconnection from their Earthboundedness (Asch et al., <span>2018</span>; Borrows, <span>2018</span>) because it extends both over peoples and lands.</p><p>I propose to consider how, from the locality of some settler states such as Canada and the United States, an intimate connection between the settlers’ claim to sovereignty, mastery and possession, and Modernity/Coloniality, is disclosed, which is significant for understanding the Anthropocene and for envisioning ways of acting otherwise that may help to remedy it. My claims regarding the Anthropocene and Modernity/Coloniality are thus perspectival; they do not pretend to offer complete and universal accounts of either, but rather hope to diagnose distinctive features of both, as experienced and disclosed from the underside of Modernity.</p><p>I see the Anthropocene, or the Age of Man, as a symptom of contemporary settler societies’ view of themselves as <i>floating free from the land</i>, to use Brian Burkhart's formulation (<span>2019</span>) and of their associated idea of Man. Man, in this context, does not refer to humanity as a whole, but rather to the Western white cis-gendered heteropatriarchal agent of Modernity/Coloniality (Mignolo, <span>2007, 2011</span>; Yusoff, <span>2018</span>) who is driven by a will to mastery and possession (Schulz, <span>2017</span>; Singh, <span>2018</span>). This Modern/Colonial Man presents himself as the universal subject, and thereby erases and disqualifies alternative ways of being human (Singh, <span>2018</span>, Chapter Introduction).</p><p>I engage with First Nation and Native American—hereafter Indigenous—political thought and movements to articulate an alternative to the un-earthbound political practices and associated subjectivity of the Man of the Anthropocene. I use Indigenous as a collective shorthand, but my focus is on the distinct political experiences, struggles, and traditions of some of the Indigenous peoples of the lands now claimed by Canada and the United States and the radical alternatives they disclose to dominant Modern/Colonial lifeways, the significance of which extends far beyond their respective contexts. Although I appeal to the distinction between Indigenous and Western thoughts, this is not to essentialize or deny the complexities of either, but in refer","PeriodicalId":51578,"journal":{"name":"Constellations-An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.7,"publicationDate":"2023-06-10","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/1467-8675.12679","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"43921512","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Constituent power: A history By LuciaRubinelli, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2020Constituent power in the European Union By MarkusPatberg, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2020 《构成力量:历史》,卢沙鲁·比内利著,剑桥:剑桥大学出版社,2020《欧盟构成力量》,马库斯帕特伯格著,牛津:牛津大学出版社,2020
IF 0.7 Pub Date : 2023-06-07 DOI: 10.1111/1467-8675.12688
Joel I Colón-Ríos
{"title":"Constituent power: A history By LuciaRubinelli, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2020Constituent power in the European Union By MarkusPatberg, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2020","authors":"Joel I Colón-Ríos","doi":"10.1111/1467-8675.12688","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-8675.12688","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":51578,"journal":{"name":"Constellations-An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.7,"publicationDate":"2023-06-07","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"44532951","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Constellations-An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1