首页 > 最新文献

Organon F最新文献

英文 中文
Normative Naturalism on Its Own Terms 规范自然主义
IF 0.5 3区 哲学 Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-04-09 DOI: 10.31577/orgf.2021.28302
Pekka Väyrynen
{"title":"Normative Naturalism on Its Own Terms","authors":"Pekka Väyrynen","doi":"10.31577/orgf.2021.28302","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.31577/orgf.2021.28302","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":43025,"journal":{"name":"Organon F","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.5,"publicationDate":"2021-04-09","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"49367813","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Real Authors and Fictional Agents 真实作者与虚构代理人
IF 0.5 3区 哲学 Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-01-28 DOI: 10.31577/ORGF.2021.28104
A. Voltolini
{"title":"Real Authors and Fictional Agents","authors":"A. Voltolini","doi":"10.31577/ORGF.2021.28104","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.31577/ORGF.2021.28104","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":43025,"journal":{"name":"Organon F","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.5,"publicationDate":"2021-01-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"49096069","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Anti-Realism about Fictional Names at Work: A New Theory for Metafictional Sentences 工作中的虚构姓名的反现实主义:元虚构句的新理论
IF 0.5 3区 哲学 Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-01-28 DOI: 10.31577/ORGF.2021.28110
L. Rouillé
In this article, I contribute to ongoing debates about the status of fictional names. The main debate in the philosophy of language focuses on whether fictional names should be thought of as non-referring terms (this is anti-realism) or referring terms (this is realism). This debate corresponds to a debate in metaphysics about the ontological status of fictional characters: the anti-realist claim that fictional characters do not exist while the realist say that they do exist in some sense. Although anti-realism is pre-theoretically intuitive, it has been challenged by a powerful argument in favour of realism based on so-called “metafictional” uses of fictional terms. This argument puts a lot of pressure on the anti-realist, for they have to come up with a theory of metafictional sentences which is in keeping with the anti-realist central tenet. I show that the existing antirealist account of metafictional statements is wrong-headed. I thus propose a new one. In doing so, I hope to free the anti-realist from the realist pressure. However, I do not offer any argument against realism. Consequently, I merely claim that anti-realism be a live
在这篇文章中,我对正在进行的关于虚构名字地位的辩论做出了贡献。语言哲学中的主要争论集中在虚构的名字是否应该被认为是非指涉术语(这是反现实主义)还是指涉术语(这是现实主义)。这种争论对应于形而上学中关于虚构人物本体论地位的争论:反现实主义者认为虚构人物不存在,而现实主义者则认为他们在某种意义上确实存在。尽管反现实主义在理论上之前是直觉的,但它已经受到了一种强有力的论点的挑战,这种论点基于对虚构术语的所谓“元虚构”使用而支持现实主义。这个论点给反现实主义者带来了很大的压力,因为他们必须提出一种符合反现实主义中心原则的元虚构句理论。我指出,现有的对元虚构陈述的反现实主义解释是错误的。因此,我提出一个新的建议。这样做,我希望将反现实主义者从现实主义者的压力中解放出来。然而,我并没有提出任何反对现实主义的论点。因此,我只是主张反现实主义是一种生活
{"title":"Anti-Realism about Fictional Names at Work: A New Theory for Metafictional Sentences","authors":"L. Rouillé","doi":"10.31577/ORGF.2021.28110","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.31577/ORGF.2021.28110","url":null,"abstract":"In this article, I contribute to ongoing debates about the status of fictional names. The main debate in the philosophy of language focuses on whether fictional names should be thought of as non-referring terms (this is anti-realism) or referring terms (this is realism). This debate corresponds to a debate in metaphysics about the ontological status of fictional characters: the anti-realist claim that fictional characters do not exist while the realist say that they do exist in some sense. Although anti-realism is pre-theoretically intuitive, it has been challenged by a powerful argument in favour of realism based on so-called “metafictional” uses of fictional terms. This argument puts a lot of pressure on the anti-realist, for they have to come up with a theory of metafictional sentences which is in keeping with the anti-realist central tenet. I show that the existing antirealist account of metafictional statements is wrong-headed. I thus propose a new one. In doing so, I hope to free the anti-realist from the realist pressure. However, I do not offer any argument against realism. Consequently, I merely claim that anti-realism be a live","PeriodicalId":43025,"journal":{"name":"Organon F","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.5,"publicationDate":"2021-01-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"42698661","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
Fictional Names and Fictional Concepts: A Moderate Fictionalist Account 虚构的名字与虚构的概念:一个适度的虚构主义者的叙述
IF 0.5 3区 哲学 Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-01-28 DOI: 10.31577/ORGF.2021.28106
Eleonora Orlando
The main thesis I want to defend in this essay is that a fictional name refers to an individual concept, understood as a mental file that stores information, in the form of different descriptive concepts, about a purported individual. Given there is no material particular a fictional name could be referring to, it will be construed as referring to the concept of a particular, with which many descriptive concepts are associated, in the context of the set of thoughts constitutive of a fictional narrative. A fictional narrative will be thus characterised as a conceptual world, namely, a set of sentence-types semantically correlated with a set of thought-types.
我想在这篇文章中捍卫的主要论点是,虚构的名字指的是一种个人概念,可以理解为一种心理文件,以不同描述性概念的形式存储有关所称个人的信息。如果一个虚构的名字没有具体的内容,那么它就会被理解为指的是一个特定的概念,在虚构叙事的思想背景下,许多描述性的概念都与之相关。因此,虚构的叙述将被表征为一个概念世界,即一组语义上与一组思想类型相关的句子类型。
{"title":"Fictional Names and Fictional Concepts: A Moderate Fictionalist Account","authors":"Eleonora Orlando","doi":"10.31577/ORGF.2021.28106","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.31577/ORGF.2021.28106","url":null,"abstract":"The main thesis I want to defend in this essay is that a fictional name refers to an individual concept, understood as a mental file that stores information, in the form of different descriptive concepts, about a purported individual. Given there is no material particular a fictional name could be referring to, it will be construed as referring to the concept of a particular, with which many descriptive concepts are associated, in the context of the set of thoughts constitutive of a fictional narrative. A fictional narrative will be thus characterised as a conceptual world, namely, a set of sentence-types semantically correlated with a set of thought-types.","PeriodicalId":43025,"journal":{"name":"Organon F","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.5,"publicationDate":"2021-01-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"43462806","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
Fictional Tellers 虚构的出纳员
IF 0.5 3区 哲学 Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-01-28 DOI: 10.31577/orgf.2021.28105
S. Predelli
{"title":"Fictional Tellers","authors":"S. Predelli","doi":"10.31577/orgf.2021.28105","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.31577/orgf.2021.28105","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":43025,"journal":{"name":"Organon F","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.5,"publicationDate":"2021-01-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"47240913","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
How Can Millians Believe in Superheroes? 数百万人怎么会相信超级英雄?
IF 0.5 3区 哲学 Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-01-28 DOI: 10.31577/ORGF.2021.28107
J. F. Lima
What is the content of beliefs expressed by sentences with fictional names? Millianism has notoriously struggled to give a satisfactory answer to this question. Some Millians have argued that fictional names are empty names. But such a view entails that the belief that Superman has impressive superpowers and the belief that Aquaman has impressive superpowers have the same content, contrary to our intuitions. Others have argued that fictional names refer to fictional entities. But this view has a long-standing problem, Frege’s Puzzle, and many philosophers are skeptical that Millians have successfully addressed it, despite commendable efforts. In this paper, I put forward a different Millian Theory of fictional proper names that by-passes these and other objections related to belief content. The novelty of my proposal partially rests on a distinction I draw between semantic content and belief content—as opposed to a distinction between belief content and belief state or a way of grasping the content, as it is commonly found in Millian accounts—in a framework where belief contents are not part of the meaning of names.
用虚构名字的句子表达信仰的内容是什么?众所周知,共和主义一直在努力为这个问题给出一个令人满意的答案。一些Millians认为虚构的名字是空的。但这样的观点意味着,超人拥有令人印象深刻的超能力的信念和水行侠拥有令人印象印象深刻的超级能力的信念有着相同的内容,这与我们的直觉相反。其他人则认为,虚构的名字指的是虚构的实体。但这种观点有一个长期存在的问题,弗雷格的难题,尽管做出了值得赞扬的努力,但许多哲学家对米利安人是否成功解决了这个问题持怀疑态度。在本文中,我提出了一个不同的虚构专有名词的米利安理论,该理论绕过了这些和其他与信仰内容有关的反对意见。我的建议的新颖性部分取决于我在语义内容和信仰内容之间的区别——而不是信仰内容和信仰状态之间的区别,或者把握内容的一种方式,就像在Millian账户中常见的那样——在一个信仰内容不属于名称含义的框架中。
{"title":"How Can Millians Believe in Superheroes?","authors":"J. F. Lima","doi":"10.31577/ORGF.2021.28107","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.31577/ORGF.2021.28107","url":null,"abstract":"What is the content of beliefs expressed by sentences with fictional names? Millianism has notoriously struggled to give a satisfactory answer to this question. Some Millians have argued that fictional names are empty names. But such a view entails that the belief that Superman has impressive superpowers and the belief that Aquaman has impressive superpowers have the same content, contrary to our intuitions. Others have argued that fictional names refer to fictional entities. But this view has a long-standing problem, Frege’s Puzzle, and many philosophers are skeptical that Millians have successfully addressed it, despite commendable efforts. In this paper, I put forward a different Millian Theory of fictional proper names that by-passes these and other objections related to belief content. The novelty of my proposal partially rests on a distinction I draw between semantic content and belief content—as opposed to a distinction between belief content and belief state or a way of grasping the content, as it is commonly found in Millian accounts—in a framework where belief contents are not part of the meaning of names.","PeriodicalId":43025,"journal":{"name":"Organon F","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.5,"publicationDate":"2021-01-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"43277624","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Fictional Names: Reference, Definiteness and Ontology 小说名称:指称性、确定性与本体论
IF 0.5 3区 哲学 Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-01-28 DOI: 10.31577/ORGF.2021.28103
M. Sainsbury
Definite linguistic expressions, for example proper names and singular and plural pronouns, are easy to introduce. Indefinite expressions may pave the way, but are not essential. It is also not essential that there be entities to which the successfully introduced definites refer. This is the underlying fact that makes fiction possible, and it gives guidance about fictional names: we have no need in general to suppose that there exist entities to which they refer. 1. Discourse referents and speculation ... the appearance of an indefinite noun phrase establishes a discourse referent just in case it justifies the occurrence of a coreferential pronoun or a definite noun phrase later in the text. ... We maintain that the problem of coreference within a discourse is a linguistic problem and can be studied independently of any general theory of extra-linguistic reference. (Kartunnen 1976) Kartunnen is focused on the way in which an indefinite noun phrase can “justify” a subsequent definite one, as in the classic example “A man came into the bar. He ordered a martini”. A singular pronoun like “he” is normally supposed to refer to a specific (male) person, and it is natural to suppose that understanding a token of the pronoun requires knowing what it refers to. In a sense, we do know what this occurrence of “he” refers to: the man who came into the bar. But more demanding tests for knowledge of reference may fail: we may have no further information to offer concerning the man, and we might be unable to distinguish him from other men. Since we understand the classic two-sentence example perfectly well, including its occurrence of “he”, these failures shows that the tests for understanding were overdemanding: understanding a definite pronoun does requires neither any substantive ability to distinguish its referent from other things nor the possession of further information concerning the referent. Furthermore, our understanding is not undermined by our ignorance of whether the two sentences are true, and whether they were uttered with full assertive seriousness, or with some non-truth-involving intention. Understanding does not require that we believe that there exists a real referent for “he”, or even that we believe the utterer believes this or wants us to believe it. A discourse referent, as I understand its role in Kartunnen’s theory, and in the Discourse Representation Theories his work inspired, is a definite mental representational vehicle, singular or plural. There may or may not be some entity or entities to which it refers (so the expression
明确的语言表达,如专有名词和单数和复数代词,很容易介绍。不确定的表达可能会铺平道路,但不是必要的。成功引入的定义词所指的实体也不是必要的。这是使虚构成为可能的基本事实,它为虚构的名字提供了指导:一般来说,我们不需要假设它们所指的实体存在。1. 话语指涉和推测……不定名词短语的出现建立了一个话语指称物,以防它证明了在文本后面出现一个指代代词或一个确定名词短语. ...我们认为语篇内的共指问题是一个语言学问题,可以独立于任何一般的语言外指称理论进行研究。(kartunen, 1976) kartunen关注的是一个不定名词短语如何“证明”一个随后的确定短语的合理性,就像在经典的例子“一个男人走进酒吧。”他点了一杯马提尼。”像“他”这样的单数代词通常被认为是指一个特定的(男性)人,很自然地,人们会认为理解代词的符号需要知道它指的是什么。从某种意义上说,我们确实知道这个“他”指的是什么:那个走进酒吧的人。但是,对参考知识的更严格的测试可能会失败:我们可能没有关于这个人的进一步信息可以提供,我们可能无法将他与其他人区分开来。由于我们完全理解经典的两句话的例子,包括它的“he”的出现,这些失败表明理解测试的要求过高:理解一个确定代词既不需要任何区分其所指物与其他事物的实质性能力,也不需要拥有关于所指物的进一步信息。此外,我们的理解不会因为我们不知道这两个句子是否真实,以及它们是带着完全自信的严肃态度说出来的,还是带着一些不真实的意图而受到损害。理解并不要求我们相信“他”存在一个真实的指涉物,甚至不要求我们相信说话者相信这一点或希望我们相信这一点。根据我的理解,话语指涉物在kartunen的理论以及他的作品所启发的话语表征理论中所扮演的角色,是一种明确的精神表征载体,可以是单数或复数。可能存在也可能不存在它所引用的某个或多个实体(因此表达式
{"title":"Fictional Names: Reference, Definiteness and Ontology","authors":"M. Sainsbury","doi":"10.31577/ORGF.2021.28103","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.31577/ORGF.2021.28103","url":null,"abstract":"Definite linguistic expressions, for example proper names and singular and plural pronouns, are easy to introduce. Indefinite expressions may pave the way, but are not essential. It is also not essential that there be entities to which the successfully introduced definites refer. This is the underlying fact that makes fiction possible, and it gives guidance about fictional names: we have no need in general to suppose that there exist entities to which they refer. 1. Discourse referents and speculation ... the appearance of an indefinite noun phrase establishes a discourse referent just in case it justifies the occurrence of a coreferential pronoun or a definite noun phrase later in the text. ... We maintain that the problem of coreference within a discourse is a linguistic problem and can be studied independently of any general theory of extra-linguistic reference. (Kartunnen 1976) Kartunnen is focused on the way in which an indefinite noun phrase can “justify” a subsequent definite one, as in the classic example “A man came into the bar. He ordered a martini”. A singular pronoun like “he” is normally supposed to refer to a specific (male) person, and it is natural to suppose that understanding a token of the pronoun requires knowing what it refers to. In a sense, we do know what this occurrence of “he” refers to: the man who came into the bar. But more demanding tests for knowledge of reference may fail: we may have no further information to offer concerning the man, and we might be unable to distinguish him from other men. Since we understand the classic two-sentence example perfectly well, including its occurrence of “he”, these failures shows that the tests for understanding were overdemanding: understanding a definite pronoun does requires neither any substantive ability to distinguish its referent from other things nor the possession of further information concerning the referent. Furthermore, our understanding is not undermined by our ignorance of whether the two sentences are true, and whether they were uttered with full assertive seriousness, or with some non-truth-involving intention. Understanding does not require that we believe that there exists a real referent for “he”, or even that we believe the utterer believes this or wants us to believe it. A discourse referent, as I understand its role in Kartunnen’s theory, and in the Discourse Representation Theories his work inspired, is a definite mental representational vehicle, singular or plural. There may or may not be some entity or entities to which it refers (so the expression","PeriodicalId":43025,"journal":{"name":"Organon F","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.5,"publicationDate":"2021-01-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"47663113","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 3
Frege’s Equivalence Thesis and Reference Failure 弗雷格的等价命题与参考失效
IF 0.5 3区 哲学 Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-01-28 DOI: 10.31577/ORGF.2021.28109
Nathan Hawkins
Frege claims that sentences of the form ‘A’ are equivalent to sentences of the form ‘it is true that A’ (The Equivalence Thesis). Frege also says that there are fictional names that fail to refer, and that sentences featuring fictional names fail to refer as a result. The thoughts such sentences express, Frege says, are also fictional, and neither true nor false. Michael Dummett argues that these claims are inconsistent. But his argument requires clarification, since there are two ways The Equivalence Thesis has been formulated, according as the thesis equates the senses or the referents of the relevant sentences. I have two aims in this paper. The first is to demonstrate that a sameness of sense thesis is inconsistent with Frege’s other theses. The second is to argue that a sameness of reference thesis is consistent with them. Thus, all else being equal, Frege ought to endorse a sameness of reference, rather than a sameness of sense thesis.
弗雷格认为形式为" A "的句子与形式为" it is true that A "的句子是等价的(等价命题)。弗雷格还说,有些虚构的名字无法指代,因此,以虚构名字为特征的句子也无法指代。弗雷格说,这些句子表达的思想也是虚构的,既不真实也不虚假。Michael Dummett认为这些说法是不一致的。但他的论点需要澄清,因为等价命题有两种表述方式,即等价命题将相关句子的意义或指称等同起来。我写这篇论文有两个目的。首先是证明意义同一性论题与弗雷格的其他论题是不一致的。二是论证参考论题的同一性与二者是一致的。因此,在其他条件相同的情况下,弗雷格应当赞同指称同一性,而不是意义同一性的论点。
{"title":"Frege’s Equivalence Thesis and Reference Failure","authors":"Nathan Hawkins","doi":"10.31577/ORGF.2021.28109","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.31577/ORGF.2021.28109","url":null,"abstract":"Frege claims that sentences of the form ‘A’ are equivalent to sentences of the form ‘it is true that A’ (The Equivalence Thesis). Frege also says that there are fictional names that fail to refer, and that sentences featuring fictional names fail to refer as a result. The thoughts such sentences express, Frege says, are also fictional, and neither true nor false. Michael Dummett argues that these claims are inconsistent. But his argument requires clarification, since there are two ways The Equivalence Thesis has been formulated, according as the thesis equates the senses or the referents of the relevant sentences. I have two aims in this paper. The first is to demonstrate that a sameness of sense thesis is inconsistent with Frege’s other theses. The second is to argue that a sameness of reference thesis is consistent with them. Thus, all else being equal, Frege ought to endorse a sameness of reference, rather than a sameness of sense thesis.","PeriodicalId":43025,"journal":{"name":"Organon F","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.5,"publicationDate":"2021-01-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"44581807","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Revisiting the ‘Wrong Kind of Object’ Problem 重新审视“错误的对象”问题
IF 0.5 3区 哲学 Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-01-28 DOI: 10.31577/ORGF.2021.28108
M. Semeijn, E. Zalta
Any uniform semantic treatment of fictional names (e.g., ‘Frodo’) across parafictional statements (e.g., ‘In The Lord of the Rings, Frodo was born in the Shire’) and metafictional statements (e.g., ‘Frodo was invented by Tolkien’) runs into a variation of the ‘wrong kind of object’ problem. The problem arises when an analysis of one of these statements inappropriately attributes a property to an object. For example, it would be problematic if an analysis implied that flesh and blood individuals are invented by someone, and similarly problematic if an analysis implied that abstract objects are born in a certain region. Abstract object theory has provided a solution to this conundrum by distinguishing two modes of predication: encoding and exemplifying. Recently Klauk has argued that the problem reappears for the analysis of explicit parafictional statements in this theory. In this paper we formalize the objection and show that one can distinguish three issues in connection with the ‘wrong kind of object’ problem. We then address them in turn. ∗Copyright c © 2020, by Merel Semeijn and Edward N. Zalta. This paper is forthcoming in Organon F. The authors would like to thank the audience at PhiLang2019, Emar Maier and two anonymous Organon F reviewers for their valuable feedback. This research is supported by the Dutch Research Council (NWO), Vidi Grant 276-80-004 (Emar Maier). Merel Semeijn and Edward N. Zalta 2 1 The ‘wrong kind of object’ problem The semantics of statements about fictions requires a distinction between four different types of statements that feature fictional names (i.e., names of fictional entities). Consider the following four statements about Frodo: (1) Frodo had a very trying time that afternoon. (2) Frodo was born in the Shire. (3) In/According to The Lord of the Rings, Frodo was born in the Shire. (4) Frodo was invented by Tolkien. We shall categorize, and subsequently refer to these statements, using the following terminology: • (1) is a fictional statement, i.e., it is part of a fictional narrative (e.g., (1) is a quote from Tolkien’s The Lord of the Rings). Such statements are usually understood as neither true nor false but rather as fictional truth-makers; the act of storytelling determines what is true in the fictional story. • (2) and (3) are parafictional statements, i.e., statements about what is true in some fiction but which are not part of the original storytelling. These statements are usually analysed as being true or false (depending on the content of the fictional story) and can be ‘explicit’ like (3) or ‘implicit’ like (2) (depending on whether the prefix ‘In/According to fiction/story s’ is overt). • (4) is a metafictional statement, i.e., a statement about a fictional entity as a fictional entity that can be true or false. Any uniform semantic treatment of fictional names across these different types of statements runs into a variation of ‘the problem of the wrong kind of object’. If we adopt a realist appr
我们通过指出故事算子创造了一个类似于命题态度报告所创造的高张力环境来解释对象论是如何解决这些问题的(第5节)。最后,我们对虚构、副虚构和元虚构陈述之间的隐含关系提出了一些见解(第6节)。2小说名称的统一语义除了区分虚构、副虚构和元虚构的陈述外,关于小说分析的讨论还引入了小说“内部”话语和小说“外部”话语之间的区别。这种区别试图将(a)从小说内部的角度描述小说内容的话语(例如,将佛罗多视为一个有血有肉的人)和(b)从小说外部的角度描述故事内容的话语分开(例如,以虚构人物的身份谈论佛罗多)。然而,我们将在下面看到,一些句子构成了“混合话语”,因为它们结合了Merel Semeijn和Edward N.Zalta 4话语的内部和外部形式。这些句子引发了一个问题,即是否有可能对内部和外部话语进行统一的语义分析。这个问题可以用于我们对句子的初步区分:是否对虚构、副虚构和元虚构的陈述进行了统一的语义分析?在下文中,我们将考察一些有利于在内部和外部话语中进行统一语义分析的论点。其次,我们将重新表述对虚构名称进行统一语义处理的必要性。事实证明,关于混合话语的文献只建立了对边缘化和元虚构陈述进行统一分析的必要性。目前尚不清楚这种渴望是否延伸到对虚构、副虚构和元虚构话语的统一分析。
{"title":"Revisiting the ‘Wrong Kind of Object’ Problem","authors":"M. Semeijn, E. Zalta","doi":"10.31577/ORGF.2021.28108","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.31577/ORGF.2021.28108","url":null,"abstract":"Any uniform semantic treatment of fictional names (e.g., ‘Frodo’) across parafictional statements (e.g., ‘In The Lord of the Rings, Frodo was born in the Shire’) and metafictional statements (e.g., ‘Frodo was invented by Tolkien’) runs into a variation of the ‘wrong kind of object’ problem. The problem arises when an analysis of one of these statements inappropriately attributes a property to an object. For example, it would be problematic if an analysis implied that flesh and blood individuals are invented by someone, and similarly problematic if an analysis implied that abstract objects are born in a certain region. Abstract object theory has provided a solution to this conundrum by distinguishing two modes of predication: encoding and exemplifying. Recently Klauk has argued that the problem reappears for the analysis of explicit parafictional statements in this theory. In this paper we formalize the objection and show that one can distinguish three issues in connection with the ‘wrong kind of object’ problem. We then address them in turn. ∗Copyright c © 2020, by Merel Semeijn and Edward N. Zalta. This paper is forthcoming in Organon F. The authors would like to thank the audience at PhiLang2019, Emar Maier and two anonymous Organon F reviewers for their valuable feedback. This research is supported by the Dutch Research Council (NWO), Vidi Grant 276-80-004 (Emar Maier). Merel Semeijn and Edward N. Zalta 2 1 The ‘wrong kind of object’ problem The semantics of statements about fictions requires a distinction between four different types of statements that feature fictional names (i.e., names of fictional entities). Consider the following four statements about Frodo: (1) Frodo had a very trying time that afternoon. (2) Frodo was born in the Shire. (3) In/According to The Lord of the Rings, Frodo was born in the Shire. (4) Frodo was invented by Tolkien. We shall categorize, and subsequently refer to these statements, using the following terminology: • (1) is a fictional statement, i.e., it is part of a fictional narrative (e.g., (1) is a quote from Tolkien’s The Lord of the Rings). Such statements are usually understood as neither true nor false but rather as fictional truth-makers; the act of storytelling determines what is true in the fictional story. • (2) and (3) are parafictional statements, i.e., statements about what is true in some fiction but which are not part of the original storytelling. These statements are usually analysed as being true or false (depending on the content of the fictional story) and can be ‘explicit’ like (3) or ‘implicit’ like (2) (depending on whether the prefix ‘In/According to fiction/story s’ is overt). • (4) is a metafictional statement, i.e., a statement about a fictional entity as a fictional entity that can be true or false. Any uniform semantic treatment of fictional names across these different types of statements runs into a variation of ‘the problem of the wrong kind of object’. If we adopt a realist appr","PeriodicalId":43025,"journal":{"name":"Organon F","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.5,"publicationDate":"2021-01-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"41825721","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
Preface 前言
IF 0.5 3区 哲学 Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-01-28 DOI: 10.31577/orgf.2021.28101
Piotr Stalmaszczyk
{"title":"Preface","authors":"Piotr Stalmaszczyk","doi":"10.31577/orgf.2021.28101","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.31577/orgf.2021.28101","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":43025,"journal":{"name":"Organon F","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.5,"publicationDate":"2021-01-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"43286807","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Organon F
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1