首页 > 最新文献

ASIAN PHILOSOPHY最新文献

英文 中文
Ren 仁 (Humaneness) and Li 禮 (Ritual) in a painting metaphor from the perspective of contextual individuality 从语境个性的角度看绘画隐喻中的“仁”与“礼”
IF 0.6 2区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-09-16 DOI: 10.1080/09552367.2021.1977464
Yuzhou Yang
ABSTRACT The contextual dimension of ren or li is celebrated in English studies of Confucian ethics. However, it often gives way to the issue of individual practice in studies concerning the relationship between ren and li due perhaps to an excessive focus on personal moral development. Inspired by a painting metaphor from the Analects, the present study reassesses this unbalanced approach to the ren-li relationship through the proposed theme of contextual individuality. In the wake of relationally constituted individuality in Confucian philosophy, this study shows that the moral endowment of caring for others in human nature, which constitutes the moral foundation of ren and li, calls for a contextually practical approach to the ren-li relationship. This approach is crucial for the recognition that one’s moral development may not be truly accomplished unless undertaken in the context of the moral development of fellow human beings.
在英语儒家伦理研究中,“仁”或“礼”的语境维度备受推崇。然而,在仁礼关系的研究中,由于过分关注个人道德发展,它往往让位给个人实践问题。本研究以《论语》中的一个绘画隐喻为灵感,通过语境个性的主题重新评估这种不平衡的人理关系。继儒家哲学中关系构成的个性之后,本研究表明,人性中关怀他人的道德禀赋构成了仁礼的道德基础,这要求我们对仁礼关系进行语境实践研究。这种方法对于认识到一个人的道德发展可能无法真正完成至关重要,除非在人类同胞道德发展的背景下进行。
{"title":"Ren 仁 (Humaneness) and Li 禮 (Ritual) in a painting metaphor from the perspective of contextual individuality","authors":"Yuzhou Yang","doi":"10.1080/09552367.2021.1977464","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/09552367.2021.1977464","url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACT The contextual dimension of ren or li is celebrated in English studies of Confucian ethics. However, it often gives way to the issue of individual practice in studies concerning the relationship between ren and li due perhaps to an excessive focus on personal moral development. Inspired by a painting metaphor from the Analects, the present study reassesses this unbalanced approach to the ren-li relationship through the proposed theme of contextual individuality. In the wake of relationally constituted individuality in Confucian philosophy, this study shows that the moral endowment of caring for others in human nature, which constitutes the moral foundation of ren and li, calls for a contextually practical approach to the ren-li relationship. This approach is crucial for the recognition that one’s moral development may not be truly accomplished unless undertaken in the context of the moral development of fellow human beings.","PeriodicalId":44358,"journal":{"name":"ASIAN PHILOSOPHY","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2021-09-16","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"46546475","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
The scope of the pramāṇas in classical and postclassical Sāṃkhya pramāṇas的范围在古典和后古典Sāṃkhya
IF 0.6 2区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-08-30 DOI: 10.1080/09552367.2021.1967571
Ołena Łucyszyna
ABSTRACT One of the lively polemics between Buddhists and Naiyāyikas is devoted to the question of whether each pramāṇa—means of knowledge—has an independent scope of validity, which does not overlap the scopes of other pramāṇas, or whether more than one pramāṇa can be applied to the same object. Dignāga and continuators of his thought defend pramāṇa-vyavasthā, ‘autonomy of [the object spheres of] pramāṇas,’ while Naiyāyikas defend the opposing conception, called pramāṇa-samplava, ‘coalescence of [the object spheres of] pramāṇas.’ Scholars usually ascribe pramāṇa-vyavasthā to Sāṃkhya. This paper explores the classical and postclassical Sāṃkhya view of the scope of the pramāṇas and shows that Sāṃkhya did not follow pramāṇa-vyavasthā. In Sāṃkhya, the scopes of perception and inference for knowing perceptible objects overlap, while inference for knowing supersensible objects and reliable verbal testimony have autonomous object spheres. However, there is also a tendency toward pramāṇa-vyavasthā in Sāṃkhya, which is in conflict with the Sāṃkhya theory of pramāṇas.
摘要佛教徒和奈伊加人之间的一场激烈争论是关于每一个pramāṇa——知识手段——有一个独立的有效范围,与其他pramā的范围不重叠ṇ作为,或者是否有一个以上的pramāṇa可以应用于同一对象。迪涅加及其思想的延续者为普拉姆辩护ṇa-vyavasthā,“普拉姆的[客体范围]的自治”ṇ正如Naiyāyikas捍卫相反的概念,称为pramāṇa-samplava,“pramā的[物体球体]的合并”ṇ学者们通常将pramāṇa-vyavasthā到Sāṃkhya。本文探讨了古典主义和后古典主义的Sāṃ克雅对普兰教范围的看法ṇ如和表明Sāṃkhya没有遵循pramāṇa-vyavasthā。在Sāṃkhya认为,认知可感对象的感知和推理范围是重叠的,而认知超可感对象和可靠的口头证词的推理具有自主的对象范围。然而,也有一种倾向于使用pramāṇ在Sāṃkhya,与Sāṃ克雅普拉姆学说ṇ像
{"title":"The scope of the pramāṇas in classical and postclassical Sāṃkhya","authors":"Ołena Łucyszyna","doi":"10.1080/09552367.2021.1967571","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/09552367.2021.1967571","url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACT One of the lively polemics between Buddhists and Naiyāyikas is devoted to the question of whether each pramāṇa—means of knowledge—has an independent scope of validity, which does not overlap the scopes of other pramāṇas, or whether more than one pramāṇa can be applied to the same object. Dignāga and continuators of his thought defend pramāṇa-vyavasthā, ‘autonomy of [the object spheres of] pramāṇas,’ while Naiyāyikas defend the opposing conception, called pramāṇa-samplava, ‘coalescence of [the object spheres of] pramāṇas.’ Scholars usually ascribe pramāṇa-vyavasthā to Sāṃkhya. This paper explores the classical and postclassical Sāṃkhya view of the scope of the pramāṇas and shows that Sāṃkhya did not follow pramāṇa-vyavasthā. In Sāṃkhya, the scopes of perception and inference for knowing perceptible objects overlap, while inference for knowing supersensible objects and reliable verbal testimony have autonomous object spheres. However, there is also a tendency toward pramāṇa-vyavasthā in Sāṃkhya, which is in conflict with the Sāṃkhya theory of pramāṇas.","PeriodicalId":44358,"journal":{"name":"ASIAN PHILOSOPHY","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2021-08-30","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"46029846","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Is Mohism really li-promotionalism? 墨家真的是利促主义吗?
IF 0.6 2区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-07-30 DOI: 10.1080/09552367.2021.1960677
Yun Wu, Amin Ebrahimi Afrouzi
ABSTRACT A longstanding orthodoxy holds that the Mohists regard the promotion of li (benefit, 利) as their ultimate normative criterion, meaning that they measure what is yi (just, 義) or buyi (unjust, 不義) depending on whether it maximizes li or not. This orthodoxy dates back at least to Joseph Edkins (1859), who saw Mozi as a utilitarian and an ally of Bentham. In this paper, we will argue that this orthodoxy should be reconsidered because it does not square with several passages from the Mozi. That the Mohists place a strong weight on the promotion of ‘li for the whole world (tianxia zhi li, 天下之利)’ is uncontroversial. We argue, however, that in certain cases the Mohist moral calculus diverges in its rationale or outcome from li-promotionalism. This position rejects the orthodoxy by showing that Mohism and li-promotionalism are not entirely coterminous.
长期以来的正统观点认为,墨家将利(利,利)的提升作为他们的最终规范标准,这意味着他们衡量什么是义(义,义)或不义(义,义)取决于它是否最大化了利。这种正统观念至少可以追溯到约瑟夫·艾德金斯(1859),他认为墨子是一个功利主义者,是边沁的盟友。在本文中,我们将论证,这种正统应该重新考虑,因为它不符合墨子的几个段落。墨家非常重视“天下之礼”的推广,这是无可争议的。然而,我们认为,在某些情况下,墨家的道德演算在其基本原理或结果上与利促主义有所不同。这一立场反对正统,表明墨家和利促主义并不完全是同源的。
{"title":"Is Mohism really li-promotionalism?","authors":"Yun Wu, Amin Ebrahimi Afrouzi","doi":"10.1080/09552367.2021.1960677","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/09552367.2021.1960677","url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACT A longstanding orthodoxy holds that the Mohists regard the promotion of li (benefit, 利) as their ultimate normative criterion, meaning that they measure what is yi (just, 義) or buyi (unjust, 不義) depending on whether it maximizes li or not. This orthodoxy dates back at least to Joseph Edkins (1859), who saw Mozi as a utilitarian and an ally of Bentham. In this paper, we will argue that this orthodoxy should be reconsidered because it does not square with several passages from the Mozi. That the Mohists place a strong weight on the promotion of ‘li for the whole world (tianxia zhi li, 天下之利)’ is uncontroversial. We argue, however, that in certain cases the Mohist moral calculus diverges in its rationale or outcome from li-promotionalism. This position rejects the orthodoxy by showing that Mohism and li-promotionalism are not entirely coterminous.","PeriodicalId":44358,"journal":{"name":"ASIAN PHILOSOPHY","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2021-07-30","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1080/09552367.2021.1960677","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"43606472","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Differences and similarities between the later-Wittgenstein’s philosophy of religion and the Islamic mystical tradition 后期维特根斯坦的宗教哲学与伊斯兰神秘主义传统的异同
IF 0.6 2区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-07-03 DOI: 10.1080/09552367.2021.1917157
Vahid Taebnia
ABSTRACT Despite all fundamental divergences, the similarities formed between some interpretations of the later-Wittgenstein’s philosophy of religion and the tradition of Islamic Mysticism (Sufism), can yet be philosophically recognized. These basic analogies are as follows: 1) The inextricability of belief and practice and the priority of practice over knowledge 2) The characterization of the core religious beliefs as the primal ground of man’s perception and understanding, in contrast to the view that considers fundamental religious beliefs as theoretical conclusions derived from purely rational courses of reflection 3) A new practice-laden narrative of religious realism. Given that, one can even shed a new Wittgensteinian light on even the most abstract and metaphysical elements of the mystical worldview. If fundamental religious beliefs are interpreted not as metaphysical doctrines but as a set of descriptions arising from a specific form of practical life, then the ability to see a sort of transcendent and sacred unity in the whole universe will be based on a way of purposive engagement and wayfaring in the natural and social world.
摘要尽管存在着根本的分歧,但对维特根斯坦宗教哲学的一些解释与伊斯兰神秘主义传统(苏菲主义)之间形成的相似之处,仍然可以在哲学上得到承认。这些基本的类比如下:1)信仰和实践的不可分割性以及实践优先于知识2)核心宗教信仰是人类感知和理解的原始基础,与将基本宗教信仰视为纯粹理性反思过程中得出的理论结论的观点相反3)宗教现实主义的新实践叙事。鉴于此,人们甚至可以对神秘世界观中最抽象和形而上学的元素进行新的维特根斯坦式的阐释。如果基本的宗教信仰不是被解释为形而上学的教义,而是由一种特定的现实生活形式产生的一系列描述,那么在整个宇宙中看到一种超越和神圣的统一的能力将建立在一种有目的的参与和在自然和社会世界中漫游的方式之上。
{"title":"Differences and similarities between the later-Wittgenstein’s philosophy of religion and the Islamic mystical tradition","authors":"Vahid Taebnia","doi":"10.1080/09552367.2021.1917157","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/09552367.2021.1917157","url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACT Despite all fundamental divergences, the similarities formed between some interpretations of the later-Wittgenstein’s philosophy of religion and the tradition of Islamic Mysticism (Sufism), can yet be philosophically recognized. These basic analogies are as follows: 1) The inextricability of belief and practice and the priority of practice over knowledge 2) The characterization of the core religious beliefs as the primal ground of man’s perception and understanding, in contrast to the view that considers fundamental religious beliefs as theoretical conclusions derived from purely rational courses of reflection 3) A new practice-laden narrative of religious realism. Given that, one can even shed a new Wittgensteinian light on even the most abstract and metaphysical elements of the mystical worldview. If fundamental religious beliefs are interpreted not as metaphysical doctrines but as a set of descriptions arising from a specific form of practical life, then the ability to see a sort of transcendent and sacred unity in the whole universe will be based on a way of purposive engagement and wayfaring in the natural and social world.","PeriodicalId":44358,"journal":{"name":"ASIAN PHILOSOPHY","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2021-07-03","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1080/09552367.2021.1917157","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"49088390","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Confucian freedom: assessing the debate 儒家自由:评估辩论
IF 0.6 2区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-07-03 DOI: 10.1080/09552367.2021.1899439
R. Carleo
ABSTRACT What place does freedom have in Confucianism? We find a wide spectrum of views on the matter: some deny that Confucians value or even conceive of freedom, while others celebrate uniquely exalted forms of Confucian freedom. This paper examines the range of proposals, finding consensus among these diverse views in that all identify distinctive Confucian emphases on (i) subjective affirmation of the good and (ii) the cultivation of desires and intentions to align with that good. The variation among views of Confucian freedom does not result from disparate interpretations of Confucian teachings. Rather, their divergence lies in affirming or denying that these core aspects of Confucian thought should be seen as ‘freedom.’ This reveals an undiscussed, fundamental question regarding Confucian freedom: Can and should we see the traditional Confucian moral ideal—that is, Confucian goodness and sagely virtue—as versions of freedom? What do we gain by doing so?
自由在儒家思想中占有什么地位?在这个问题上,我们发现了各种各样的观点:一些人否认儒家重视甚至设想自由,而另一些人则赞扬儒家独特的崇高形式的自由。本文考察了这些建议的范围,在这些不同的观点中找到了共识,因为它们都认同儒家对(i)对善的主观肯定和(ii)对与善一致的欲望和意图的培养的独特强调。儒家自由观的差异并非源于对儒家教义的不同解读。相反,他们的分歧在于肯定或否认儒家思想的这些核心方面应该被视为“自由”。这揭示了一个未被讨论的、关于儒家自由的基本问题:我们是否可以、是否应该把传统儒家的道德理想——即儒家的善和贤德——视为自由的不同版本?我们这样做有什么好处呢?
{"title":"Confucian freedom: assessing the debate","authors":"R. Carleo","doi":"10.1080/09552367.2021.1899439","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/09552367.2021.1899439","url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACT What place does freedom have in Confucianism? We find a wide spectrum of views on the matter: some deny that Confucians value or even conceive of freedom, while others celebrate uniquely exalted forms of Confucian freedom. This paper examines the range of proposals, finding consensus among these diverse views in that all identify distinctive Confucian emphases on (i) subjective affirmation of the good and (ii) the cultivation of desires and intentions to align with that good. The variation among views of Confucian freedom does not result from disparate interpretations of Confucian teachings. Rather, their divergence lies in affirming or denying that these core aspects of Confucian thought should be seen as ‘freedom.’ This reveals an undiscussed, fundamental question regarding Confucian freedom: Can and should we see the traditional Confucian moral ideal—that is, Confucian goodness and sagely virtue—as versions of freedom? What do we gain by doing so?","PeriodicalId":44358,"journal":{"name":"ASIAN PHILOSOPHY","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2021-07-03","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1080/09552367.2021.1899439","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"45972574","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 4
Wang Yangming, Descartes, and the Sino-European juncture of Enlightenment 王阳明、笛卡尔与中欧启蒙运动的交汇点
IF 0.6 2区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-07-03 DOI: 10.1080/09552367.2021.1919368
Zemian Zheng
ABSTRACT Wang Yangming is the founder of Chinese Enlightenment in the Ming-Qing period, in a similar way Descartes is for the European. The European Enlightenment thinkers such as Leibniz and Voltaire had been inspired by China about the human being’s ethical independence at the collective level, namely, the ability of a community to lead an ethical life independent of God’s revelation. Meanwhile, the Enlightenment thinkers failed to notice the Chinese intellectual resources that encourage human being’s ethical independence at the individual level, namely, the belief that every human individual is equally capable of leading one’s ethical life purely relying on one’s own good judgment. For this point, Wang Yangming is the resources that the West could have drawn upon. Both Wang Yangming and Descartes assert the egalitarianism about every individual’s power of judgment. I label this similarity as the ‘Sino-European juncture of Enlightenment.’ Other similarities between these two thinkers lie, firstly, in their common strategy in defending egalitarianism: both give a psychological account of the sources of error by analyzing the relationship between will and reason; and secondly, in their methodology: both redefine the method of attaining knowledge, and both emphasize that one should start from the plain, simple and insignificant things and then ascend to the complex things at issue.
摘要王阳明是明清时期中国启蒙运动的奠基人,与笛卡尔对欧洲人的启蒙思想如出一辙。欧洲启蒙思想家莱布尼茨和伏尔泰受到中国的启发,认为人类在集体层面上具有伦理独立性,即一个群体有能力过上独立于上帝启示的伦理生活。同时,启蒙思想家没有注意到中国在个人层面鼓励人类伦理独立的智力资源,即相信每个人都有同样的能力纯粹依靠自己的良好判断来领导自己的伦理生活。在这一点上,王阳明是西方可以利用的资源。王阳明和笛卡尔都主张对每个人的判断能力的平等主义。我把这种相似性称为“中欧启蒙运动的交汇点”这两位思想家的其他相似之处在于,首先,他们捍卫平等主义的共同策略:都通过分析意志和理性之间的关系,从心理学上解释了错误的根源;二是在方法论上:既重新定义了获得知识的方法,又强调从平淡、简单、琐碎的事物出发,再上升到复杂的事物。
{"title":"Wang Yangming, Descartes, and the Sino-European juncture of Enlightenment","authors":"Zemian Zheng","doi":"10.1080/09552367.2021.1919368","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/09552367.2021.1919368","url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACT Wang Yangming is the founder of Chinese Enlightenment in the Ming-Qing period, in a similar way Descartes is for the European. The European Enlightenment thinkers such as Leibniz and Voltaire had been inspired by China about the human being’s ethical independence at the collective level, namely, the ability of a community to lead an ethical life independent of God’s revelation. Meanwhile, the Enlightenment thinkers failed to notice the Chinese intellectual resources that encourage human being’s ethical independence at the individual level, namely, the belief that every human individual is equally capable of leading one’s ethical life purely relying on one’s own good judgment. For this point, Wang Yangming is the resources that the West could have drawn upon. Both Wang Yangming and Descartes assert the egalitarianism about every individual’s power of judgment. I label this similarity as the ‘Sino-European juncture of Enlightenment.’ Other similarities between these two thinkers lie, firstly, in their common strategy in defending egalitarianism: both give a psychological account of the sources of error by analyzing the relationship between will and reason; and secondly, in their methodology: both redefine the method of attaining knowledge, and both emphasize that one should start from the plain, simple and insignificant things and then ascend to the complex things at issue.","PeriodicalId":44358,"journal":{"name":"ASIAN PHILOSOPHY","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2021-07-03","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1080/09552367.2021.1919368","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"46732235","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Non-humans in the Zhuangzi: Animalism and anti-anthropocentrism 庄子中的非人:动物主义与反人类中心主义
IF 0.6 2区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-06-03 DOI: 10.1080/09552367.2021.1934218
P. D’Ambrosio
ABSTRACT Some argue that animals and non-human figures in the Zhuangzi help displace the significance of humans. According to others the Zhuangzi suggests a certain time of ‘animalism,’ asking us to be more like various types of fauna and flora that do not share our self-centeredness. In this paper the use of non-human characters in the Zhuangzi will be examined through a survey of traditional Chinese commentary, comparisons with the Lunyu, and placing the use of non-human characters within the larger context of the Zhuangzi. Thus we find that while anti-anthropocentric and animalistic perspectives can be philosophized with the Zhuangzi, the text itself is not overly concerned with these subjects. Animals and non-human characters are mainly allegorical or metaphorical, allowing the Zhuangzito 1) make broadly applicable arguments; 2) playfully discuss ideas that may be unappealing at first glance, and; 3) create a distance that allows the text to resist ossification.
摘要有人认为《庄子》中的动物和非人形象有助于取代人类的意义。根据其他人的说法,《庄子》暗示了一个“动物主义”的时代,要求我们更像各种各样的动物和植物,而不是以我们自己为中心。本文将通过对中国传统评论的调查,与《论说》进行比较,并将非人字的使用置于《庄子》的大背景下,来考察《庄子》中非人字的用法。因此,我们发现,虽然反人类中心主义和动物主义的观点可以用《庄子》来哲学化,但文本本身并没有过度关注这些主题。动物和非人的性格主要是寓言或隐喻的,允许庄子1)提出广泛适用的论点;2) 开玩笑地讨论乍一看可能没有吸引力的想法;3) 创造一个距离,让文本抵抗僵化。
{"title":"Non-humans in the Zhuangzi: Animalism and anti-anthropocentrism","authors":"P. D’Ambrosio","doi":"10.1080/09552367.2021.1934218","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/09552367.2021.1934218","url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACT Some argue that animals and non-human figures in the Zhuangzi help displace the significance of humans. According to others the Zhuangzi suggests a certain time of ‘animalism,’ asking us to be more like various types of fauna and flora that do not share our self-centeredness. In this paper the use of non-human characters in the Zhuangzi will be examined through a survey of traditional Chinese commentary, comparisons with the Lunyu, and placing the use of non-human characters within the larger context of the Zhuangzi. Thus we find that while anti-anthropocentric and animalistic perspectives can be philosophized with the Zhuangzi, the text itself is not overly concerned with these subjects. Animals and non-human characters are mainly allegorical or metaphorical, allowing the Zhuangzito 1) make broadly applicable arguments; 2) playfully discuss ideas that may be unappealing at first glance, and; 3) create a distance that allows the text to resist ossification.","PeriodicalId":44358,"journal":{"name":"ASIAN PHILOSOPHY","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2021-06-03","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1080/09552367.2021.1934218","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"42345504","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 4
Eastern and Western creativity of tradition 东西方传统的创造性
IF 0.6 2区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-05-27 DOI: 10.1080/09552367.2021.1933735
Conrong Wang, Qiduan Chen
ABSTRACT Western creativity is usually entrusted to the human imagination, regarded as a mental power capable of envisioning eternally original artefacts, while in the East creativity is entrusted to nature-in-the human, what Taoist philosophy calls qi, a spiritual power capable of reflecting the passing changes of nature in paintings, poems, and other forms of art. It is the intention of this paper to explore and elucidate these differences between the Western and Eastern conceptualizations of creativity, ending with a suggestion of one feature they may have in common.
西方的创造力通常被赋予人类的想象力,被认为是一种能够永远想象原创艺术品的精神力量,而在东方,创造力被赋予人的自然,道教哲学称之为气,一种能够在绘画、诗歌和其他艺术形式中反映自然变化的精神力量。本文的目的是探讨和阐明西方和东方的创造力概念之间的这些差异,最后提出他们可能有一个共同的特征。
{"title":"Eastern and Western creativity of tradition","authors":"Conrong Wang, Qiduan Chen","doi":"10.1080/09552367.2021.1933735","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/09552367.2021.1933735","url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACT Western creativity is usually entrusted to the human imagination, regarded as a mental power capable of envisioning eternally original artefacts, while in the East creativity is entrusted to nature-in-the human, what Taoist philosophy calls qi, a spiritual power capable of reflecting the passing changes of nature in paintings, poems, and other forms of art. It is the intention of this paper to explore and elucidate these differences between the Western and Eastern conceptualizations of creativity, ending with a suggestion of one feature they may have in common.","PeriodicalId":44358,"journal":{"name":"ASIAN PHILOSOPHY","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2021-05-27","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1080/09552367.2021.1933735","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"48812956","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
Existence as a first-order predicate: Themes from Mirdamad 作为一阶谓词的存在性:来自Mirdamad的主题
IF 0.6 2区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-05-14 DOI: 10.1080/09552367.2021.1928201
Davood Hosseini
ABSTRACT Mirdamad, a prominent philosopher of the Late Medieval Period active in the Islamic world, regards existence as nothing in reality. In this paper, I employ methods devised by contemporary analytic philosophers to reinterpret his theory of existence. Based on my interpretation, this theory of existence has many aspects. Metaphysically, existence is nothing in reality. In effect, it is not a property of individuals. Logically, ‘existence’ is a first-order predicate. In order to make these two claims consistent, he develops a sparse theory of properties, proposes an analysis of the meaning of ‘existence’, appeals to a meta-metaphysical view about the language of metaphysics, develops a truthmaker theory of truth, and commits to a specific theory of grounding. Arguably, this theory of existence seems to be tenable from a contemporary analytic perspective.
摘要活跃于伊斯兰世界的中世纪晚期著名哲学家米尔达马德认为存在在现实中是虚无的。在这篇论文中,我采用了当代分析哲学家设计的方法来重新解释他的存在论。根据我的理解,这种存在论有很多方面。在形而上学上,存在在现实中毫无意义。实际上,它不是个人的财产。从逻辑上讲,“存在”是一个一阶谓词。为了使这两种主张一致,他发展了一种稀疏的性质理论,提出了对“存在”意义的分析,呼吁对形而上学语言的元形而上学观点,发展了真理的真理论,并致力于一种特定的基础理论。可以说,从当代分析的角度来看,这种存在论似乎是站得住脚的。
{"title":"Existence as a first-order predicate: Themes from Mirdamad","authors":"Davood Hosseini","doi":"10.1080/09552367.2021.1928201","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/09552367.2021.1928201","url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACT Mirdamad, a prominent philosopher of the Late Medieval Period active in the Islamic world, regards existence as nothing in reality. In this paper, I employ methods devised by contemporary analytic philosophers to reinterpret his theory of existence. Based on my interpretation, this theory of existence has many aspects. Metaphysically, existence is nothing in reality. In effect, it is not a property of individuals. Logically, ‘existence’ is a first-order predicate. In order to make these two claims consistent, he develops a sparse theory of properties, proposes an analysis of the meaning of ‘existence’, appeals to a meta-metaphysical view about the language of metaphysics, develops a truthmaker theory of truth, and commits to a specific theory of grounding. Arguably, this theory of existence seems to be tenable from a contemporary analytic perspective.","PeriodicalId":44358,"journal":{"name":"ASIAN PHILOSOPHY","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2021-05-14","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1080/09552367.2021.1928201","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"44121863","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Historical materialism in medieval China: The cases of Liu Zongyuan (773-819) and Li Gou (1009-1059) 中世纪中国的唯物史观:以柳宗元(773-819)和李构(1009-1059)为例
IF 0.6 2区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-05-07 DOI: 10.1080/09552367.2021.1924437
Dawid Rogacz
ABSTRACT It is commonly assumed that historical materialism was first developed by Karl Marx, whose philosophy is often equated with this idea. The following paper challenges this opinion by showing that historical materialism, understood as a general position within the philosophy of history, can be traced back to two generally unheralded Chinese thinkers: Liu Zongyuan (773–819) and Li Gou (1009–1059). Historical materialism is here understood as a standpoint built on three tenets: (1) a belief in the dependence of culture on the material fundaments of social life; (2) the interpretation of human history through the prism of structural transformations; and (3) understanding political and economic relationships in terms of antagonism between social groups. After elaborating upon the presence of these tenets in the thought of Liu and Li, the paper analyzes the influence of their ideas and, finally, points out the main differences between the premodern and modern forms of historical materialism.
人们通常认为历史唯物主义是由卡尔·马克思首先提出的,马克思的哲学常常与这一思想等同起来。下面这篇文章通过展示历史唯物主义,作为历史哲学中的一个普遍立场,可以追溯到两个通常不知名的中国思想家:柳宗元(773-819)和李gou(1009-1059),来挑战这种观点。历史唯物主义在这里被理解为建立在三个原则之上的立场:(1)相信文化依赖于社会生活的物质基础;(2)通过结构转变的棱镜解读人类历史;(3)从社会群体之间的对抗来理解政治和经济关系。本文在阐述了这些原则在刘黎思想中的存在之后,分析了他们思想的影响,最后指出了前现代和现代形式的历史唯物主义的主要区别。
{"title":"Historical materialism in medieval China: The cases of Liu Zongyuan (773-819) and Li Gou (1009-1059)","authors":"Dawid Rogacz","doi":"10.1080/09552367.2021.1924437","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/09552367.2021.1924437","url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACT It is commonly assumed that historical materialism was first developed by Karl Marx, whose philosophy is often equated with this idea. The following paper challenges this opinion by showing that historical materialism, understood as a general position within the philosophy of history, can be traced back to two generally unheralded Chinese thinkers: Liu Zongyuan (773–819) and Li Gou (1009–1059). Historical materialism is here understood as a standpoint built on three tenets: (1) a belief in the dependence of culture on the material fundaments of social life; (2) the interpretation of human history through the prism of structural transformations; and (3) understanding political and economic relationships in terms of antagonism between social groups. After elaborating upon the presence of these tenets in the thought of Liu and Li, the paper analyzes the influence of their ideas and, finally, points out the main differences between the premodern and modern forms of historical materialism.","PeriodicalId":44358,"journal":{"name":"ASIAN PHILOSOPHY","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2021-05-07","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1080/09552367.2021.1924437","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"41532387","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 3
期刊
ASIAN PHILOSOPHY
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1