首页 > 最新文献

Journal of Social Philosophy最新文献

英文 中文
Social pathologies of informational privacy 信息隐私的社会病态
IF 1.1 3区 哲学 Q3 ETHICS Pub Date : 2022-12-21 DOI: 10.1111/josp.12504
Wulf Loh
<p>Following the recent practice turn in privacy research, informational privacy is increasingly analyzed with regard to the “appropriate flow of information” within a given practice, which preserves the “contextual integrity” of that practice (Nissenbaum, <span>2010</span>, p. 149; <span>2015</span>). Such a practice-theoretical take on privacy emphasizes the normative structure of practices as well as its structural injustices and power asymmetries, rather than focusing on the intentions and moral considerations of individual or institutional actors. Since privacy norms are seen to be institutionalized via the role obligations of the practice's participants, this approach can analyze structural and systematic privacy infringements in terms of “defective role performances and defective social relations” (Roessler & Mokrosinska, <span>2013</span>, p. 780).</p><p>Unfortunately, it is still often somewhat unclear what this exactly means within the context of informational privacy, why these performances and relations are defective and for whom. This raises the common objection of a so-called “practice positivism” (Applbaum, <span>1999</span>, p. 51), that is, the difficulty of practice–theoretical accounts to take a practice-independent standpoint, from which to normatively evaluate the existing practice norms themselves. For example, Nissenbaum herself initially argues for a “presumption in favor of the status quo” with respect to the appropriateness and flow of privacy norms within a practice (Nissenbaum, <span>2004</span>, p. 127). Such a “practice conservatism” (Nissenbaum, <span>2010</span>, p. 169) comes dangerously close to committing a naturalistic fallacy, if not undergirded by practice-external criteria (which is ultimately what she does).</p><p>Merely resorting to existing practice norms to assess what defective role performances amount to, only shifts the question from how to recognize an appropriate flow of information to the question of how to recognize those defective role performances and social relations. Against this backdrop, the central aim of this article is to shed light on this question without resorting to practice-independent first principles or far-reaching universalistic anthropological assumptions. For this, I will analyze the notion of “defective role performances and social relations” in terms of social pathologies.<sup>1</sup> Doing so has two advantages: First of all, it can draw on already existing concepts and distinctions, which help to categorize the different levels of analysis that exist in informational privacy research and situate the notion of “defective role performances” within them (Section 1). Second, those concepts and distinctions can serve as a basis for establishing a typology of phenomena with regard to deficient practices of informational privacy (Section 4).</p><p>Having thus set the scene in Section 1, I can move on to address the notion of “defective role performances and social relations” w
在相应的数据化子实践中,所有 BCR 都承认对方是标准权威,从而确立并维持了实践的 "标准权威"。正如我在上文所论证的,这意味着所有数据收集主体和数据化主体相互承认对方批评他人角色表演的权威,并由此承认数据化实践的结构本身。在一个信息私有的实践中,所有数据化主体由于在相应的数据化子实践中具有标准权威,因此有权质疑、争辩并要求为其数据的系统收集、存储、处理和传播提供正当理由。凭借这种权威,他们可以有效地解释这种做法,从而可以复制并改变这种做法。但这并不意味着他们的权威必须始终得到遵守,才能称之为 "私人 "数据化实践。什么是实践中的 "适当信息流",仍然取决于普遍接受的实践规范。由此可见,标准权威的概念并不是指一种理想的话语环境,在这种环境中,所有参与者都是平等的(Habermas, 1986; Habermas, 2001)15。尽管如此,正如医生的例子所显示的,相互冲突的解释往往会被明确化(Brandom, 1998; Celikates, 2018)。在病理实践中,往往正是这种明确化的能力,被错误地承认为实践参与者中的某一部分是标准权威而扭曲了。正如我在上一节中所阐述的,这种承认需要(a)对数据化子实践中其他 BCR 的角色表演提出质疑的权威;以及(b)要求他们为自己对角色义务的解释提供正当理由。如第 1 节所述,"结构性 "和 "系统性 "指的是持久和全面的缺陷,这些缺陷通常会影响到数据化子实践中的所有或大部分行为者--或者说,正如我们现在可以具体说明的那样,影响到数据化子实践中的一种或多种业连管。通过将斯塔尔关于标准权威的论述移植到信息隐私领域,SORM给出了诊断层面的答案,即 "什么是信息隐私的社会病理学 "这一问题的答案。尽管如此,我们仍然需要评估为什么这些对标准权威的结构性和系统性错误认知会构成一种社会病理学。答案与社会实践的内在运作息息相关:社会实践依赖于这种相互承认:(a) 其稳定相互行为预期的能力;(b) 其逐步调整这些预期内容的能力。在社会实践中,参与者不断地相互批评,从而解释、确定角色行为并使之正常化(Berger &amp; Luckmann, 1967; Giddens, 1984)。这些解释即行为在复制实践的同时也在逐步改变实践:它捕捉到了社会实践中的规范因素,而这正是社会实践整合的原因(哈贝马斯,1986 年,第 2 卷;洛克伍德,1964 年),因此,一方面,它将社会实践与巧合的一致行为区分开来,另一方面,它又将社会实践与单纯的强制协调区分开来。没有这种认可,第 2 节中定义的社会实践就不可能存在,因为从长远来看,它们将失去可重复性,也就是说,它们不可能在内部稳定下来,也不可能适应不断变化的规范解释。如果没有这种信念(以内化的 "知道-诀窍 "的形式),就不会出现规范性地约束参与者的共同实践(哈特,1994 年,第 89 页)。唯一可以通过社会整合实现稳定的形式是来自实践外部的强制或协调力量。此外,解释--行为--之间的不断往返不仅解释了角色义务是如何演变和正常化的,也解释了它们是如何随着时间的推移而变化的。总之,作为标准权威的相互承认是可复制性(在整合、稳定和适应性的意义上)的必要条件,从而也是数据化实践发挥作用的必要条件。
{"title":"Social pathologies of informational privacy","authors":"Wulf Loh","doi":"10.1111/josp.12504","DOIUrl":"10.1111/josp.12504","url":null,"abstract":"&lt;p&gt;Following the recent practice turn in privacy research, informational privacy is increasingly analyzed with regard to the “appropriate flow of information” within a given practice, which preserves the “contextual integrity” of that practice (Nissenbaum, &lt;span&gt;2010&lt;/span&gt;, p. 149; &lt;span&gt;2015&lt;/span&gt;). Such a practice-theoretical take on privacy emphasizes the normative structure of practices as well as its structural injustices and power asymmetries, rather than focusing on the intentions and moral considerations of individual or institutional actors. Since privacy norms are seen to be institutionalized via the role obligations of the practice's participants, this approach can analyze structural and systematic privacy infringements in terms of “defective role performances and defective social relations” (Roessler &amp; Mokrosinska, &lt;span&gt;2013&lt;/span&gt;, p. 780).&lt;/p&gt;&lt;p&gt;Unfortunately, it is still often somewhat unclear what this exactly means within the context of informational privacy, why these performances and relations are defective and for whom. This raises the common objection of a so-called “practice positivism” (Applbaum, &lt;span&gt;1999&lt;/span&gt;, p. 51), that is, the difficulty of practice–theoretical accounts to take a practice-independent standpoint, from which to normatively evaluate the existing practice norms themselves. For example, Nissenbaum herself initially argues for a “presumption in favor of the status quo” with respect to the appropriateness and flow of privacy norms within a practice (Nissenbaum, &lt;span&gt;2004&lt;/span&gt;, p. 127). Such a “practice conservatism” (Nissenbaum, &lt;span&gt;2010&lt;/span&gt;, p. 169) comes dangerously close to committing a naturalistic fallacy, if not undergirded by practice-external criteria (which is ultimately what she does).&lt;/p&gt;&lt;p&gt;Merely resorting to existing practice norms to assess what defective role performances amount to, only shifts the question from how to recognize an appropriate flow of information to the question of how to recognize those defective role performances and social relations. Against this backdrop, the central aim of this article is to shed light on this question without resorting to practice-independent first principles or far-reaching universalistic anthropological assumptions. For this, I will analyze the notion of “defective role performances and social relations” in terms of social pathologies.&lt;sup&gt;1&lt;/sup&gt; Doing so has two advantages: First of all, it can draw on already existing concepts and distinctions, which help to categorize the different levels of analysis that exist in informational privacy research and situate the notion of “defective role performances” within them (Section 1). Second, those concepts and distinctions can serve as a basis for establishing a typology of phenomena with regard to deficient practices of informational privacy (Section 4).&lt;/p&gt;&lt;p&gt;Having thus set the scene in Section 1, I can move on to address the notion of “defective role performances and social relations” w","PeriodicalId":46756,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Social Philosophy","volume":"55 3","pages":"541-561"},"PeriodicalIF":1.1,"publicationDate":"2022-12-21","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/josp.12504","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"42251597","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
You can't tell me what to do! Why should states comply with international institutions? 你无权对我指手画脚!各国为什么要遵守国际机构?
IF 0.8 3区 哲学 Q3 ETHICS Pub Date : 2022-12-18 DOI: 10.1111/josp.12503
Antoinette Scherz
The tension between the authority of states and the authority of international institutions is a persistent feature of international relations. Legitimacy assessments of international institutions play a crucial role in resolving such tensions. If an international institution exercises legitimate authority, it creates binding obligations for states. According to Raz’s well-known service conception, legitimate authority depends on the reasons for actions of those who are subject to it. Yet what are the practical reasons that should guide the actions of states? Can states be bound by international institutions on all kinds of issues or are certain issues exempted because of sovereignty considerations? This paper argues that self-regarding reasons cannot ground political authority with the respective demand for compliance. Since reasons for states concern individuals both inside and outside of their jurisdiction and other state peoples, self-regarding reasons for states, which form a domain of personal pursuits or sovereign decisions, are highly restricted.
国家权威和国际机构权威之间的紧张关系是国际关系的一个持久特征。对国际机构的合法性评估在解决这种紧张局势方面发挥着至关重要的作用。如果一个国际机构行使合法权力,它就为各国规定了具有约束力的义务。根据拉兹著名的服务理念,合法权力取决于受其约束的人的行动理由。然而,指导国家行动的实际理由是什么?国家能否在各种问题上受到国际机构的约束,或者某些问题是否因主权考虑而被豁免?本文认为,自我考虑的原因不能将政治权威与各自的合规要求联系起来。由于国家的理由涉及其管辖范围内外的个人和其他国家人民,国家的自我考虑理由构成了个人追求或主权决定的领域,因此受到高度限制。
{"title":"You can't tell me what to do! Why should states comply with international institutions?","authors":"Antoinette Scherz","doi":"10.1111/josp.12503","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/josp.12503","url":null,"abstract":"The tension between the authority of states and the authority of international institutions is a persistent feature of international relations. Legitimacy assessments of international institutions play a crucial role in resolving such tensions. If an international institution exercises legitimate authority, it creates binding obligations for states. According to Raz’s well-known service conception, legitimate authority depends on the reasons for actions of those who are subject to it. Yet what are the practical reasons that should guide the actions of states? Can states be bound by international institutions on all kinds of issues or are certain issues exempted because of sovereignty considerations? This paper argues that self-regarding reasons cannot ground political authority with the respective demand for compliance. Since reasons for states concern individuals both inside and outside of their jurisdiction and other state peoples, self-regarding reasons for states, which form a domain of personal pursuits or sovereign decisions, are highly restricted.","PeriodicalId":46756,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Social Philosophy","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.8,"publicationDate":"2022-12-18","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"45996494","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
Neither race nor ethnicity: Latinidad as a social affordance 既不是种族,也不是民族:拉丁裔是一种社会优势
IF 1.1 3区 哲学 Q3 ETHICS Pub Date : 2022-12-16 DOI: 10.1111/josp.12500
Alejandro Arango, Adam Burgos
{"title":"Neither race nor ethnicity: Latinidad as a social affordance","authors":"Alejandro Arango,&nbsp;Adam Burgos","doi":"10.1111/josp.12500","DOIUrl":"10.1111/josp.12500","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":46756,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Social Philosophy","volume":"55 3","pages":"502-521"},"PeriodicalIF":1.1,"publicationDate":"2022-12-16","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"42955357","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Tying ourselves to the mast, or acting for the sake of justice? Ethos, individual duties, and social sanctions 把自己绑在桅杆上,还是为了正义而行动?社会风气、个人责任和社会制裁
IF 1.1 3区 哲学 Q3 ETHICS Pub Date : 2022-12-15 DOI: 10.1111/josp.12502
Markus Furendal
<p>Political philosophy often focuses on what the state may legitimately do to, or in the name of, its citizens. Yet, how well a society lives up to political-philosophical ideals arguably also depends on the decisions that individuals make in their daily lives regarding, for instance, how to treat others, what to work with, and how to spend their free time. Many contemporary social movements for increased justice hence seem to focus less on reforming institutions and laws, and instead attempt to change the values and principles that individuals accept and act on. In political-philosophical terms, these movements are less interested in the “basic structure” of a society, and more intent on changing its “ethos.”<sup>1</sup> Part of this change could happen by influencing what people think are reasonable principles of justice, but the efforts to reform what is seen as acceptable behavior often also involves individuals monitoring each other and issuing positive and negative sanctions in response to each other's actions. Recent years have seen social media and other technological developments boosting the power of such sanctions, allowing millions of strangers to join in the criticism of particular wrongdoers. More recently, the COVID-19 pandemic brought these kinds of social mechanisms to the center of attention, as decentralized and informal monitoring and sanctioning of people's response to pandemic-related regulations appeared to be at least as important as more classical forms of state enforcement. This article assumes that there are, indeed, moral demands on individuals to act in certain ways not only in times of crisis but also in order to further a just society, and sets out and defends an account of the concept of ethos that helps to conceptualize how individual compliance with these demands can be encouraged, or enforced.</p><p>The assumption that the degree of justice in a society does not only depend on how its institutions are set up is closely associated with philosopher G. A. Cohen's influential critique of John Rawls. The core of their disagreement is that, while Rawls suggests that principles of justice apply primarily to the major political and economic institutions of a society—its basic structure—Cohen argues that principles of justice would also shape a social ethos that inspires citizens to act in particular ways in their daily lives. Specifically, Cohen is skeptical of Rawls's willingness to accept as just equality-upsetting economic incentives that motivate individuals to work productively. Rejecting authoritarian attempts to coerce people to contribute, Cohen suggests that justice rather requires an egalitarian ethos that inspires and motivates individuals to make certain decisions about how much to work and with what.<sup>2</sup> Such an ethos, Cohen suggests, is a “moral climate,”<sup>3</sup> or “… a structure of response lodged in the motivations that inform everyday life …,”<sup>4</sup> that somehow influences individual
相应地,理解我所说的道德风尚的一种方式是,当一个群体的成员将某一特定原则内化并按照该原则行事时,该群体就存在特定的道德风尚。根据道德哲学和政治哲学,随后的第 3 节指出,这与政治哲学中经常提出的完全遵守的理想化假设类似,实际上使道德风尚的概念在功能上等同于罗尔斯的观点,即正义社会中的公民会表现出正义感。借鉴社会规范的哲学理论和心理学研究,第 4 节阐述了我所说的社会风气的机制,即当一个群体的成员坚持一种分散的非正式社会制裁制度,从而提高他们对某一特定原则的遵守程度时,该群体就会形成一种特定的社会风气。将这两种观点结合起来似乎很有吸引力,我们可以假定,当道德伦理无法充分激励人们时,社会伦理就会作为一种外部机制发挥作用,由我们强加给自己以帮助我们实现目标,就像尤利西斯要求他的船员把他绑在桅杆上一样。然而,第 5 节探讨了可能会阻碍我们实现目标的两难困境。我们可能既有理论上的理由,也有实践上的理由去关心人们出于正义的原因去做正义的事,而试图依靠社会伦理来提高个人的道德动机可能会挤掉个人实现正义所需的道德动机。我最终得出的结论是,这是一个虚假的两难境地,因为重要的是我们在行动时部分地(但不一定仅仅是)受到正义的驱使。只要人们出于道德原因致力于支持社会制裁体系,就可以因为制裁而遵守道德要求。第 6 节讨论了人们经常提到的担忧,即伦理所涉及的那种社会制裁会威胁到个人自由,最后一节作了简短的总结。风气有时也用来指某个职业(如教师或医生)的核心价值观和中心指导原则,或者小团体或整个社会的性格和态度。9 例如,我们可以说斯堪的纳维亚国家具有平等主义的风气,或者资本主义的风气是个人主义的。这是一种描述性的说法。但是,正如我们经常用个人的道德品质来解释其行为--比如 "坏苹果 "无视道德标准,或者 "圣人 "超越道德标准的要求--在解释群体成员的行为时,我们也经常引用群体的精神气质。例如,我们可以说,瑞典更加平等主义的风气导致瑞典比风气不同的国家容忍更高的税收。10 因此,风气的概念不仅仅是对人们所信奉的原则和价值观的描述,而且作为解释性陈述的一部分,它还可以帮助我们理解人们为什么要这样做。11 现在,任何社会显然都有许多理想、原则和价值观,但为了便于讨论,我将做三个简化的假设。首先,我将主要讨论基于特定道德原则的一元论等12 ,而不是基于若干道德原则的多元论等。其次,虽然本节讨论的是伦理概念本身,但文章的其余部分则明确涉及分析正义伦理如何发挥作用。第三,关于原则与义务等概念之间的关系,人们的共识少得令人吃惊,我无法在此对这一问题进行探讨。本文将经常使用这两个概念的同义词,我可以简单地指出,我将把原则作为一个更广泛的概念来对待,它既可以被解释为对权利特征的说明,也可以被解释为一种决策程序。因此,适用于个人的特定正义义务就是要求个人以特定正义原则所规定的方式行事。本文认为,伦理的作用在于鼓励个人这样做。这些定义相当专业,与该术语的通俗用法有些出入。例如,我注意到,ethos(精神)一词经常被用来指一组密切相关的规范,或一个群体特有的原则和价值观的集合。在我看来,特定的原则和价值观并不构成风气,尽管风气总是基于特定的原则和价值观。
{"title":"Tying ourselves to the mast, or acting for the sake of justice? Ethos, individual duties, and social sanctions","authors":"Markus Furendal","doi":"10.1111/josp.12502","DOIUrl":"10.1111/josp.12502","url":null,"abstract":"&lt;p&gt;Political philosophy often focuses on what the state may legitimately do to, or in the name of, its citizens. Yet, how well a society lives up to political-philosophical ideals arguably also depends on the decisions that individuals make in their daily lives regarding, for instance, how to treat others, what to work with, and how to spend their free time. Many contemporary social movements for increased justice hence seem to focus less on reforming institutions and laws, and instead attempt to change the values and principles that individuals accept and act on. In political-philosophical terms, these movements are less interested in the “basic structure” of a society, and more intent on changing its “ethos.”&lt;sup&gt;1&lt;/sup&gt; Part of this change could happen by influencing what people think are reasonable principles of justice, but the efforts to reform what is seen as acceptable behavior often also involves individuals monitoring each other and issuing positive and negative sanctions in response to each other's actions. Recent years have seen social media and other technological developments boosting the power of such sanctions, allowing millions of strangers to join in the criticism of particular wrongdoers. More recently, the COVID-19 pandemic brought these kinds of social mechanisms to the center of attention, as decentralized and informal monitoring and sanctioning of people's response to pandemic-related regulations appeared to be at least as important as more classical forms of state enforcement. This article assumes that there are, indeed, moral demands on individuals to act in certain ways not only in times of crisis but also in order to further a just society, and sets out and defends an account of the concept of ethos that helps to conceptualize how individual compliance with these demands can be encouraged, or enforced.&lt;/p&gt;&lt;p&gt;The assumption that the degree of justice in a society does not only depend on how its institutions are set up is closely associated with philosopher G. A. Cohen's influential critique of John Rawls. The core of their disagreement is that, while Rawls suggests that principles of justice apply primarily to the major political and economic institutions of a society—its basic structure—Cohen argues that principles of justice would also shape a social ethos that inspires citizens to act in particular ways in their daily lives. Specifically, Cohen is skeptical of Rawls's willingness to accept as just equality-upsetting economic incentives that motivate individuals to work productively. Rejecting authoritarian attempts to coerce people to contribute, Cohen suggests that justice rather requires an egalitarian ethos that inspires and motivates individuals to make certain decisions about how much to work and with what.&lt;sup&gt;2&lt;/sup&gt; Such an ethos, Cohen suggests, is a “moral climate,”&lt;sup&gt;3&lt;/sup&gt; or “… a structure of response lodged in the motivations that inform everyday life …,”&lt;sup&gt;4&lt;/sup&gt; that somehow influences individual","PeriodicalId":46756,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Social Philosophy","volume":"55 3","pages":"522-540"},"PeriodicalIF":1.1,"publicationDate":"2022-12-15","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/josp.12502","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"42492413","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Reparations for White supremacy? Charles W. Mills and reparative vs. distributive justice after the structural turn 对白人至上主义的赔偿?查尔斯·w·米尔斯与结构性转变后的补偿性正义与分配正义
IF 0.8 3区 哲学 Q3 ETHICS Pub Date : 2022-12-09 DOI: 10.1111/josp.12499
Jennifer M. Page
{"title":"Reparations for White supremacy? Charles W. Mills and reparative vs. distributive justice after the structural turn","authors":"Jennifer M. Page","doi":"10.1111/josp.12499","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/josp.12499","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":46756,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Social Philosophy","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.8,"publicationDate":"2022-12-09","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"47723449","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
What is wrong with persecution 迫害有什么错
IF 0.8 3区 哲学 Q3 ETHICS Pub Date : 2022-11-10 DOI: 10.1111/josp.12496
Rebecca Buxton
<p>The fact that persecution is seriously wrong should be obvious. Many of the worst events in human history were acts of persecution. During the reign of the Roman Empire, Christians were beaten, murdered, and forced to fight with wild animals. Until recently, Black Americans were hunted down by mobs and lynched by their compatriots.<sup>1</sup> They were often publicly hanged, but some were also burned alive, thrown from tall buildings, and dismembered. The centuries long persecution of Jewish people culminated in the terroristic policies of Nazi Germany and the murders of over six million Jews between 1941 and 1945. These individuals were violently targeted for their perceived membership in a particular social, religious, or political group. We know already, then, that persecution is a terrible injustice. What is not obvious, however, is <i>why</i> exactly this is the case. This might immediately seem like a ridiculous proposition: persecution often involves discrimination, cruelty, extreme violence, and mass murder. Surely we know that persecution is wrong precisely because it involves acts of the worst possible kind? This paper argues that the entire picture of the wrongness of persecution cannot be understood by pointing to these individual elements alone. To put it more strongly, persecution is wrong not only when (or because) it includes these other wrongs. Instead, I argue that part of the wrongness of persecution is located in the condition that it creates for the persecuted, but also for society more generally. In doing so, I follow two similar interventions from David Sussman (2004) on torture and Lea Ypi (<span>2013</span>) on colonialism.<sup>2</sup> Both papers begin with the intuition that such acts are serious wrongs. Their aim is to offer a new way of understanding why this is so. Like Ypi's, my title does not include a question mark. I ask you to accept that there is <i>something</i> wrong with persecution. My aim is to offer a new way of understanding what that something is.</p><p>As such, I will not consider whether persecution is <i>ever</i> justified. There are (at least) two political philosophers who maintain that persecution is compatible with legitimate governance. For St. Augustine (395AD), heretical persecution is “righteous” when the Church inflicts it upon “the impious.” This is what he calls “persecution in the spirit of love.”<sup>3</sup> Such persecution was therefore viewed as a legitimate way of punishing those who have strayed from God (Christenson, <span>1968</span>).<sup>4</sup> For Hobbes, persecution is a necessary power of the Sovereign, best described as an extension of the rights of war. Hobbes distinguishes between punishment and persecution: punishment being for misdemeanors committed within the boundaries of the commonwealth and persecution being suffered by those outside it. This “right of nature to make war” extends to all individuals who refuse to be subjected under the sovereign, even citizens. P
然而,纯粹的自然灾害不能算作迫害,尽管武器化的环境危害或受害者被拒绝援助可以算作迫害。第二,迫害根据某些特征挑选出要伤害的个人:《难民公约》规定,必须因为某人的种族、宗教、国籍或某一特定社会群体的成员身份而施加迫害。第三,迫害必须“残酷”或“严重”。因此,大多数司法管辖区都同意,迫害不同于“单纯的”歧视或骚扰。2003年,美国第九巡回上诉法院的Nagoulko诉INS案讨论了因宗教信仰而被解雇是否构成迫害在这种情况下,索赔人在一段合理的时间内在其他地方找到了稳定的工作。法院的结论是,这种伤害不够严重,不足以构成迫害。因此,个人可以受到歧视,而不会受到迫害。然而,持续和系统地拒绝就业,使人们无法获得最低限度的体面生计,可以(也应该)被解释为一种迫害形式。一些司法管辖区接受这种做法。《澳大利亚移民法》(1958年)规定了迫害的一般特征,指出严重伤害的情况可能包括对人的生命或自由的威胁、严重的身体骚扰、严重的身体虐待、严重的经济困难、剥夺获得基本服务的机会以及剥夺任何谋生能力英国内政部(2016,16)也认为,如果歧视“对相关人员造成足够严重的后果”,就可以构成迫害。当然,歧视和迫害之间的界限仍然模糊而复杂;“纯粹的”歧视和迫害之间的区别往往带有政治色彩重要的是,一些偶发伤害的严重程度——例如,一次酷刑——通常被认为足以构成迫害。英国内政部也接受这一点。在穆斯塔法·多默斯诉内政部国务秘书一案(2000年)中,法院裁定“持续是迫害的通常标准,但不是普遍标准。”17因此,依靠其普通含义来定义迫害,通常会导致对迫害的理解,即迫害是基于特定(歧视性)原因针对某人的严重伤害(无论是集中的还是偶发的)。《维也纳条约法公约》还规定,除了一般意义方法外,必须根据有关论文的上下文和目的解释词语。这种关注导致了难民法中迫害的另一个更广泛的概念:国家保护方法的失败。这种模式的捍卫者认为,《难民公约》的意义和目的是为那些国家辜负了他们的人提供保护。例如,Anker(2017,184)认为,“国家的合法性[是]基于其保护公民基本需求和权利的能力和义务。这一观点在詹姆斯·哈撒韦的人权方法中得到了巩固,该方法将人权法的传统与国际难民法结合起来。根据这种观点,庇护是一种替代保护。因此,迫害被定义为“持续或系统地剥夺基本人权,表明国家保护的失败”(Hathaway和Foster, 2014, 185)近年来,一些司法管辖区采取了人权方针。欧洲议会(European Parliament)在2011年的资格指令(Qualification Directive)中指出,迫害是一种“就其性质或重复而言,严重到构成严重侵犯人权的伤害”。20英国上议院在2000年霍瓦特诉内政部国务大臣案中也同样赞同这种做法。21当然,将迫害的定义集中在保护难民的目的上,是否有助于将迫害与特定的国际法体系分开考虑,这是一个悬而未决的问题。这是否为我们指明了正确的方向,以对付-à-vis更普遍的迫害,还有待观察对于一个更普遍的政治迫害理论,我们可能很难在这样一个框架内单独工作。因此,为了超越迫害与难民保护制度的相关性来描述迫害,我将采用一种普通的语言方法,尽管我将在后面回到国家保护的重要性。重要的是,这并不意味着我不赞同在难民保护范围内采取人权办法。它的意思是,当我在这里思考迫害时,我希望能够将讨论与特定的国际公约及其法律历史分开。从这次讨论中可以得出一些初步的结论。 首先,在这种情况下,可能仍然存在我们到目前为止所关注的那种歧视,只是不那么明显。家庭暴力在某种程度上是性别的,这使它成为一种歧视(和迫害),即使丈夫和妻子的规模较小使这种镜头感觉不合适当我们放大到两个人之间的关系时,家庭暴力的主要危害似乎不是歧视,但从更广泛的意义上看,基于性别的暴力可以表明,我们仍然有权利将这些案件视为对妇女的歧视形式。其次,歧视是否需要依赖于一个人是女性、有色人种或同性恋等事实,这一点并不明显。当然,许多形式的歧视都是这种形式。但我们也可以从更广泛的角度来理解歧视的概念。丈夫可以说是在迫害他的妻子,因为他把她挑出来虐待。从这个意义上说,妻子被追求、被追捕、被挑出来。如果迫害在手段上具有歧视性,那么,我们只能认为它不具有普遍性。当然,这是理解歧视的另一种方式,需要更多的理由。我在这里要说的是,把迫害看作是歧视至少是可行的,因为它不是完全随机的。邻居的情况可能会稍微复杂一些,特别是如果我们想象一个人只是恐吓他的邻居,不管他们是谁。我们可以说这是一种迫害,即使邻居并没有歧视。这意味着并非所有的迫害案件都涉及歧视。对此的一种回应方式是简单地宣称,一个不论其品质如何都能一视同仁地伤害所有人的人,显然不是一个迫害者,尽管他们可能同样糟糕。我们在这里使用的“逼迫”一词可能不是字面意思。所以,虽然坏邻居可能会把别人的生活变成人间地狱,但迫害可能不是描述这里发生的事情的正确方式。其次,我们也可以简单地接受,在我们的日常语言中,并不是每一个“迫害”一词的实例都涉及歧视:邻居的案例是这个规则的一个罕见的例外正如我前面说过的,我在这里的目的并不是要提供一个关于迫害的无懈可击的描述,而只是要表明,迫害往往具有我们目前没有认识到的影响。这一切都是为了澄清,我在这里谈论的大多数形式的迫害都会以一种很大程度上直接的方式涉及歧视,但这些例外情况并不会破坏更普遍的说法。第三种解释迫害的错误本质的可能方法来自政治避难理论。把注意力集中在这一讨论上,与我早先提出的我们应该超越难民保护制度的特殊性的主张是矛盾的。然而,将避难的政治理论与它在国际法中的发展相对照,可以提供一个稍微不同的观点。为难民保护制度中特殊的迫害场所辩护的政治理论家认为,这相当于否认一个人作为其政治社区成员的地位。因此,迫害本质上是一种放逐。根据Price(2009, 243)的说法,难民“不仅面临着身体完整或自由的威胁;他们实际上也被驱逐出自己的政治团体。他们不仅是受害者,也是流亡者。“36受迫害个人的原籍国已拒绝其成员资格(Owen, 2020, 32)剥夺成员资格——被理解为丧失有效公民身份——至少有两个原因令人担忧(Buxton, 2021)首先,它违反了个人先前在特定社区中得到承认和保护的要求。那些遭受迫害的人通常是有强烈权利被纳入特定国家或群体的公民。迫害不仅通过发出这样的信号来破坏这种成员资格,表明这样的个人不值得保护他们的权利,而且还积极地拒绝这种保护。例如,美国黑人不仅要求作为人的平等待遇,而且要求作为美国人的平等待遇。他们的遭遇使他们无法要求加入一个有系统地建立在剥削他们基础上的政治团体。因此,正如Shklar(1993,181)所说,“政府……经常滥用其管辖范围内的居民,剥夺他们的政治成员资格和其他权利,而不是作为法律惩罚,而是因为他们属于一个被认为天生不适合纳入的群体。”39其次,拒绝成员资格违反了我们全球治理体系内的所有个人都需要在某个地方成为成员的条件。 莉亚·哈默斯坦(Leah Hammerstein)是一名持假证件在德国一家医院工作的犹太妇女,她将这种经历描述为“完全孤立、完全孤独……你身处人群之中,却像独自一人在孤岛上。”没有人能帮你寻求帮助。你不能问[原文如此]。征求意见。你必须在很短的时间内独自做出危及生命
{"title":"What is wrong with persecution","authors":"Rebecca Buxton","doi":"10.1111/josp.12496","DOIUrl":"10.1111/josp.12496","url":null,"abstract":"&lt;p&gt;The fact that persecution is seriously wrong should be obvious. Many of the worst events in human history were acts of persecution. During the reign of the Roman Empire, Christians were beaten, murdered, and forced to fight with wild animals. Until recently, Black Americans were hunted down by mobs and lynched by their compatriots.&lt;sup&gt;1&lt;/sup&gt; They were often publicly hanged, but some were also burned alive, thrown from tall buildings, and dismembered. The centuries long persecution of Jewish people culminated in the terroristic policies of Nazi Germany and the murders of over six million Jews between 1941 and 1945. These individuals were violently targeted for their perceived membership in a particular social, religious, or political group. We know already, then, that persecution is a terrible injustice. What is not obvious, however, is &lt;i&gt;why&lt;/i&gt; exactly this is the case. This might immediately seem like a ridiculous proposition: persecution often involves discrimination, cruelty, extreme violence, and mass murder. Surely we know that persecution is wrong precisely because it involves acts of the worst possible kind? This paper argues that the entire picture of the wrongness of persecution cannot be understood by pointing to these individual elements alone. To put it more strongly, persecution is wrong not only when (or because) it includes these other wrongs. Instead, I argue that part of the wrongness of persecution is located in the condition that it creates for the persecuted, but also for society more generally. In doing so, I follow two similar interventions from David Sussman (2004) on torture and Lea Ypi (&lt;span&gt;2013&lt;/span&gt;) on colonialism.&lt;sup&gt;2&lt;/sup&gt; Both papers begin with the intuition that such acts are serious wrongs. Their aim is to offer a new way of understanding why this is so. Like Ypi's, my title does not include a question mark. I ask you to accept that there is &lt;i&gt;something&lt;/i&gt; wrong with persecution. My aim is to offer a new way of understanding what that something is.&lt;/p&gt;&lt;p&gt;As such, I will not consider whether persecution is &lt;i&gt;ever&lt;/i&gt; justified. There are (at least) two political philosophers who maintain that persecution is compatible with legitimate governance. For St. Augustine (395AD), heretical persecution is “righteous” when the Church inflicts it upon “the impious.” This is what he calls “persecution in the spirit of love.”&lt;sup&gt;3&lt;/sup&gt; Such persecution was therefore viewed as a legitimate way of punishing those who have strayed from God (Christenson, &lt;span&gt;1968&lt;/span&gt;).&lt;sup&gt;4&lt;/sup&gt; For Hobbes, persecution is a necessary power of the Sovereign, best described as an extension of the rights of war. Hobbes distinguishes between punishment and persecution: punishment being for misdemeanors committed within the boundaries of the commonwealth and persecution being suffered by those outside it. This “right of nature to make war” extends to all individuals who refuse to be subjected under the sovereign, even citizens. P","PeriodicalId":46756,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Social Philosophy","volume":"54 2","pages":"201-217"},"PeriodicalIF":0.8,"publicationDate":"2022-11-10","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/josp.12496","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"44701690","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The market ideology conception of fetishism: An interpretation and defense 拜物教的市场意识形态概念:解读与辩护
IF 0.8 3区 哲学 Q3 ETHICS Pub Date : 2022-11-01 DOI: 10.1111/josp.12497
Antoine Louette
{"title":"The market ideology conception of fetishism: An interpretation and defense","authors":"Antoine Louette","doi":"10.1111/josp.12497","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/josp.12497","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":46756,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Social Philosophy","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.8,"publicationDate":"2022-11-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"42952180","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Democratic equality and higher education: Moving from access to completion 民主平等与高等教育:从入学到毕业
IF 0.8 3区 哲学 Q3 ETHICS Pub Date : 2022-10-17 DOI: 10.1111/josp.12495
Tammy Harel Ben-Shahar, Sigal Ben-Porath, Dustin Webster
{"title":"Democratic equality and higher education: Moving from access to completion","authors":"Tammy Harel Ben-Shahar,&nbsp;Sigal Ben-Porath,&nbsp;Dustin Webster","doi":"10.1111/josp.12495","DOIUrl":"10.1111/josp.12495","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":46756,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Social Philosophy","volume":"54 3","pages":"404-420"},"PeriodicalIF":0.8,"publicationDate":"2022-10-17","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"48846989","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The wrongs, harms, and ineffectiveness of torture: A moral evaluation from empirical neuroscience 酷刑的错误、伤害和无效性:来自经验神经科学的道德评价
IF 0.8 3区 哲学 Q3 ETHICS Pub Date : 2022-10-02 DOI: 10.1111/josp.12494
N. Al‐Rodhan
{"title":"The wrongs, harms, and ineffectiveness of torture: A moral evaluation from empirical neuroscience","authors":"N. Al‐Rodhan","doi":"10.1111/josp.12494","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/josp.12494","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":46756,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Social Philosophy","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.8,"publicationDate":"2022-10-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"46831880","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Contributors 贡献者
IF 0.8 3区 哲学 Q3 ETHICS Pub Date : 2022-09-26 DOI: 10.1111/josp.12420
{"title":"Contributors","authors":"","doi":"10.1111/josp.12420","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/josp.12420","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":46756,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Social Philosophy","volume":"53 3","pages":"294-295"},"PeriodicalIF":0.8,"publicationDate":"2022-09-26","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"134814661","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Journal of Social Philosophy
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1