首页 > 最新文献

The International Journal of Ethics最新文献

英文 中文
The "Unique" Quality Goodness -- A Myth “独一无二”的品质善良——一个神话
Pub Date : 1937-01-01 DOI: 10.1086/intejethi.47.2.2989335
Barnett Savery
W T HE PROPOSE to show that the evidence for the view that there is a "unique" quality goodness is overwhelmingly negative. Before this is done it is best to sketch the generic types of meanings of goodness that are possible. The meanings of goodness can be divided into two main classes: goodness has either a unique meaning or a "nonunique" meaning. If goodness has a unique meaning, then goodness is simply goodness, and it cannot be described in non-value terms. The meaning could be simple or complex, i.e., its content could be either unanalyzable or analyzable. Adherents of the unique views of goodness have usually maintained that goodness is unanalyzable. If goodness has a non-unique meaning, then goodness is describable in non-value terms. Again goodness could be either simple or complex. If goodness is simple it could mean pleasantness (assuming that pleasantness is an unanalyzable quality); or if goodness is complex, it could mean positive-interest-in-objects, etc. The meanings of goodness can again be divided into two classes: goodness has either an absolute or a relative meaning. If goodness is absolute, then there is one and only one valid meaning of goodness; but if goodness is relative, then there is one meaning of generic goodness and n specific meanings of goodness. (As in geometry, we have a generic meaning of geometry but many specific geometries.) Where goodness is relative, generic goodness is the determinable, it acts as a variable; the specific meanings of goodness are the determinates of the variable. The determinable, generic goodness, has a significant range of determinates and each determinate generates a specific value-system.
他提出要证明,存在一种“独特的”善的观点的证据绝对是消极的。在此之前,最好先勾勒出善良可能的一般含义。善良的意义可以分为两大类:善良要么具有独特的意义,要么具有“非独特”的意义。如果善良有一个独特的意义,那么善良就是善良,它不能用无价值的术语来描述。意义可以是简单的,也可以是复杂的,即其内容可以是不可分析的,也可以是可分析的。善的独特观点的拥护者通常认为善是不可分析的。如果善具有非唯一的意义,那么善就可以用非价值术语来描述。善良可以是简单的,也可以是复杂的。如果善良是简单的,它可能意味着愉悦(假设愉悦是一种不可分析的品质);或者如果善良是复杂的,它可能意味着对物体的积极兴趣,等等。善的意义又可以分为两类:善有绝对意义或相对意义。如果善是绝对的,那么善就有且只有一个有效的意义;但如果善良是相对的,那么善良就有一个一般意义和n个特定意义。(就像在几何学中一样,我们有几何学的一般含义,但有许多特定的几何学。)善良是相对的,一般的善良是可决定的,它是一个变量;善的具体含义是变量的决定因素。可决定的,一般的善,有很大范围的决定因素,每个决定因素产生一个特定的价值体系。
{"title":"The \"Unique\" Quality Goodness -- A Myth","authors":"Barnett Savery","doi":"10.1086/intejethi.47.2.2989335","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1086/intejethi.47.2.2989335","url":null,"abstract":"W T HE PROPOSE to show that the evidence for the view that there is a \"unique\" quality goodness is overwhelmingly negative. Before this is done it is best to sketch the generic types of meanings of goodness that are possible. The meanings of goodness can be divided into two main classes: goodness has either a unique meaning or a \"nonunique\" meaning. If goodness has a unique meaning, then goodness is simply goodness, and it cannot be described in non-value terms. The meaning could be simple or complex, i.e., its content could be either unanalyzable or analyzable. Adherents of the unique views of goodness have usually maintained that goodness is unanalyzable. If goodness has a non-unique meaning, then goodness is describable in non-value terms. Again goodness could be either simple or complex. If goodness is simple it could mean pleasantness (assuming that pleasantness is an unanalyzable quality); or if goodness is complex, it could mean positive-interest-in-objects, etc. The meanings of goodness can again be divided into two classes: goodness has either an absolute or a relative meaning. If goodness is absolute, then there is one and only one valid meaning of goodness; but if goodness is relative, then there is one meaning of generic goodness and n specific meanings of goodness. (As in geometry, we have a generic meaning of geometry but many specific geometries.) Where goodness is relative, generic goodness is the determinable, it acts as a variable; the specific meanings of goodness are the determinates of the variable. The determinable, generic goodness, has a significant range of determinates and each determinate generates a specific value-system.","PeriodicalId":346392,"journal":{"name":"The International Journal of Ethics","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1937-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"114187516","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Conscience and Calculation 良心与算计
Pub Date : 1937-01-01 DOI: 10.1086/INTEJETHI.47.2.2989333
V. M. Ames
HE ethical question of what an action or attitude should be depends upon the needs and interests, the values, of the persons involved. Values are vague and incalculable, but the urgency of acting with reference to them makes it a desideratum to state them in definite terms. An illusion of success in this undertaking arises from the fact that a quantitative scheme can be imposed to some extent upon the most elusive qualities. But to inflict numbers on values does not reduce them to figures; nor does the convenience of dealing with quantities avoid the ultimate inconvenience of their being derivative and deceptive. Especially dubious is the effort to be scientific in ethics, in the sense of transforming innumerable inner factors of feeling and desire into uniform integers amenable to computation. It is interesting how superficially successful the attempt can be, how much it is tacitly accepted and trusted, and how hard it is to relinquish. The alternative seems to be admission that morality is subjective, that it cannot be submitted to any objective, external criterion, that each must solve moral problems for himself by his own feeling or conscience, and grant the same privilege to everyone else-or bow to convention, authority, or some other form of arbitrary force. In practice we compromise among three ideas: that morality is a matter of private feeling, that it is acceptance of social pressure, and that it is based on a calculation of consequences to determine the greater good or the lesser evil in every puzzling situation. The advantage of putting ethics into numerical terms is that number is impartial whereas feeling and authority probably are not. The difference between a larger and a smaller number is objective; all can accept it. But this impersonal measuring stick
一个行为或态度应该是什么样的道德问题取决于相关人员的需要、兴趣和价值观。价值是模糊的,无法计算的,但是根据它们采取行动的紧迫性,使我们有必要明确地说明它们。在这项工作中,一种成功的错觉来自于这样一个事实,即定量方案可以在某种程度上强加于最难以捉摸的品质。但是把数字加在价值上并不会把它们简化为数字;处理数量的便利也不能避免它们的衍生性和欺骗性的最终不便。尤其值得怀疑的是在伦理学上的科学努力,在将无数的内在情感和欲望因素转化为可计算的统一整数的意义上。有趣的是,这种尝试在表面上是多么成功,它在多大程度上被默认和信任,而放弃又是多么困难。另一种选择似乎是承认道德是主观的,它不能屈从于任何客观的、外部的标准,每个人都必须用自己的感觉或良心为自己解决道德问题,并赋予其他人同样的特权——或者屈服于习俗、权威或其他形式的专制力量。在实践中,我们在三种观念之间妥协:道德是一种私人情感,是对社会压力的接受,是基于对后果的计算,在每一个令人困惑的情况下决定更大的善或较小的恶。用数字来表达道德的好处是,数字是公正的,而感觉和权威可能不是。较大数字和较小数字之间的差别是客观的;所有人都可以接受。但是这个客观的标尺
{"title":"Conscience and Calculation","authors":"V. M. Ames","doi":"10.1086/INTEJETHI.47.2.2989333","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1086/INTEJETHI.47.2.2989333","url":null,"abstract":"HE ethical question of what an action or attitude should be depends upon the needs and interests, the values, of the persons involved. Values are vague and incalculable, but the urgency of acting with reference to them makes it a desideratum to state them in definite terms. An illusion of success in this undertaking arises from the fact that a quantitative scheme can be imposed to some extent upon the most elusive qualities. But to inflict numbers on values does not reduce them to figures; nor does the convenience of dealing with quantities avoid the ultimate inconvenience of their being derivative and deceptive. Especially dubious is the effort to be scientific in ethics, in the sense of transforming innumerable inner factors of feeling and desire into uniform integers amenable to computation. It is interesting how superficially successful the attempt can be, how much it is tacitly accepted and trusted, and how hard it is to relinquish. The alternative seems to be admission that morality is subjective, that it cannot be submitted to any objective, external criterion, that each must solve moral problems for himself by his own feeling or conscience, and grant the same privilege to everyone else-or bow to convention, authority, or some other form of arbitrary force. In practice we compromise among three ideas: that morality is a matter of private feeling, that it is acceptance of social pressure, and that it is based on a calculation of consequences to determine the greater good or the lesser evil in every puzzling situation. The advantage of putting ethics into numerical terms is that number is impartial whereas feeling and authority probably are not. The difference between a larger and a smaller number is objective; all can accept it. But this impersonal measuring stick","PeriodicalId":346392,"journal":{"name":"The International Journal of Ethics","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1937-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"132583521","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 3
De Amicitia
Pub Date : 1937-01-01 DOI: 10.1086/intejethi.47.2.2989336
R. Lodge
IT IS hard to define friendship, to delimit it to this or that sharply outlined class of things or feelings or activities. Aristotle, past master of logical technique, in defining it as a "moral virtue," placed it among the activities with the distinctive characteristic of being participated in by two or more persons in common. Persons who live together, who participate in the same life-activities, are friends. This is in accordance with common sense. But Aristotle goes further, and interprets the situation in the light of his own philosophical interests. He recognizes three typically distinct forms of activity in which men participate in common. There is pleasure, pursued by all who are young or unreflective. There is profit, pursued by older or cooler heads, as in business. And there is philosophy, pursued by the reflective, the rational, and the wise. Associations based upon pleasure, partnerships based upon profit, are not entirely genuine forms of friendship. Each partner is out for all he can get, and such associations are essentially competitive, grasping, selfish. If either can get more out of the association than his partner, he will; and if either thinks he can get more out of a different association, he will dissolve his former partnership. Youth and the glamor of simple illusions may conceal, for a time, the essential disunion. But in the end the principle of individualism, "each for self, and none for all," works itself out; and it becomes recognized that such associations contain within themselves the seeds of their own dissolution. Such pseudo-friendships are essentially accidental. True friendship is based upon reason-the highest of human faculties. Truth is inexhaustible, and its pursuit brings value to all who care for the things of the mind. The discovery and contemplation of the secrets of nature are essentially co-operative, non-competitive. Thought alone is pure, and a society of human beings, devoted to the pursuit of truth, rests upon a basis which can never be contaminated by envy, hatred, malice, and a narrow selfishness. With the growth of years such associations grow stronger, more intimate, more divine, more nearly like the life of God, "pure thought thinking itself." Such a society was the Pythagorean brotherhood, wherein lovers of wisdom were first called "philoso-
很难给友谊下定义,也很难把它界定为这样或那样的事物、感情或活动。亚里士多德,过去的逻辑技巧大师,在将其定义为“道德美德”时,将其置于具有两个或两个以上共同参与的独特特征的活动中。生活在一起,参加同样的生活活动的人是朋友。这是符合常识的。但亚里士多德走得更远,根据他自己的哲学兴趣来解释这种情况。他认识到人们共同参与的三种典型的截然不同的活动形式。有一种快乐,所有的年轻人或不深思熟虑的人都在追求。就像在商业中一样,年长或头脑冷静的人追求利润。还有一种哲学,是由深思者、理性者和智者追求的。以快乐为基础的交往,以利益为基础的伙伴关系,都不完全是真正的友谊。每一个合作伙伴都是为了得到他所能得到的一切,这种关系本质上是竞争的,贪婪的,自私的。如果任何一方能从合作中获得比他的伙伴更多的东西,他就会这么做;如果其中任何一方认为他可以从另一个协会中获得更多,他将解散他以前的合作伙伴关系。青春和单纯幻想的魅力可能暂时掩盖了本质上的分裂。但最终,个人主义的原则——“人人为自己,无人为所有人”——发挥了作用;人们认识到,这种联系本身包含着导致其自身解体的种子。这种虚假的友谊本质上是偶然的。真正的友谊建立在理性的基础上——理性是人类最高的才能。真理是取之不尽的,对它的追求给所有关心精神事物的人带来价值。发现和思考自然的秘密本质上是合作的,而不是竞争的。只有思想才是纯洁的,一个致力于追求真理的人类社会是建立在一个永远不会被嫉妒、仇恨、恶意和狭隘的自私所污染的基础上的。随着年龄的增长,这种联系变得更强烈,更亲密,更神圣,更像上帝的生活,“纯粹的思想思想本身。”这样的社会就是毕达哥拉斯式的兄弟会,在那里,热爱智慧的人最初被称为“哲学家”
{"title":"De Amicitia","authors":"R. Lodge","doi":"10.1086/intejethi.47.2.2989336","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1086/intejethi.47.2.2989336","url":null,"abstract":"IT IS hard to define friendship, to delimit it to this or that sharply outlined class of things or feelings or activities. Aristotle, past master of logical technique, in defining it as a \"moral virtue,\" placed it among the activities with the distinctive characteristic of being participated in by two or more persons in common. Persons who live together, who participate in the same life-activities, are friends. This is in accordance with common sense. But Aristotle goes further, and interprets the situation in the light of his own philosophical interests. He recognizes three typically distinct forms of activity in which men participate in common. There is pleasure, pursued by all who are young or unreflective. There is profit, pursued by older or cooler heads, as in business. And there is philosophy, pursued by the reflective, the rational, and the wise. Associations based upon pleasure, partnerships based upon profit, are not entirely genuine forms of friendship. Each partner is out for all he can get, and such associations are essentially competitive, grasping, selfish. If either can get more out of the association than his partner, he will; and if either thinks he can get more out of a different association, he will dissolve his former partnership. Youth and the glamor of simple illusions may conceal, for a time, the essential disunion. But in the end the principle of individualism, \"each for self, and none for all,\" works itself out; and it becomes recognized that such associations contain within themselves the seeds of their own dissolution. Such pseudo-friendships are essentially accidental. True friendship is based upon reason-the highest of human faculties. Truth is inexhaustible, and its pursuit brings value to all who care for the things of the mind. The discovery and contemplation of the secrets of nature are essentially co-operative, non-competitive. Thought alone is pure, and a society of human beings, devoted to the pursuit of truth, rests upon a basis which can never be contaminated by envy, hatred, malice, and a narrow selfishness. With the growth of years such associations grow stronger, more intimate, more divine, more nearly like the life of God, \"pure thought thinking itself.\" Such a society was the Pythagorean brotherhood, wherein lovers of wisdom were first called \"philoso-","PeriodicalId":346392,"journal":{"name":"The International Journal of Ethics","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1937-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"133765649","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 6
The Changes in Fichte's Attitude Toward State Intervention in Education 费希尔对国家干预教育态度的转变
Pub Date : 1937-01-01 DOI: 10.1086/intejethi.47.2.2989338
G. Turnbull
{"title":"The Changes in Fichte's Attitude Toward State Intervention in Education","authors":"G. Turnbull","doi":"10.1086/intejethi.47.2.2989338","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1086/intejethi.47.2.2989338","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":346392,"journal":{"name":"The International Journal of Ethics","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1937-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"122453163","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Shorter Notices 较短的通知
Pub Date : 1937-01-01 DOI: 10.1086/intejethi.47.2.2989348
{"title":"Shorter Notices","authors":"","doi":"10.1086/intejethi.47.2.2989348","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1086/intejethi.47.2.2989348","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":346392,"journal":{"name":"The International Journal of Ethics","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1937-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"115994233","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
An Ethical Definition of Community 社区的伦理定义
Pub Date : 1937-01-01 DOI: 10.1086/intejethi.47.2.2989331
J. A. Clark
T, THE classical iterature of the sciences of society very readily illustrates the proposition that in this general field of thought a distinction between what actually is and what ought to be is both important and peculiarly difficult to maintain correctly. For example, Rousseau surely had a point deserving consideration when he accused Grotius (and by implication, it seems, Hobbes) of "establishing right by fact. 12 Rousseau then sought quite deliberately to base his own normative theory of society upon something else than any mere "record of past abuses," even if, with the insight of genius, he did find an account of social origins, though admittedly a partially fanciful one, important in the exposition of his own views.3 And yet, as Professor MacIver has argued, the critic himself committed an error not unlike the one he had criticized when he allowed his own vision to be circumscribed by the conspicuous actuality of the state to the extent of failing to see a wider, if less obvious, pattern of relationships-to which MacIver applies the term
社会科学的经典文献很容易说明这样一个命题:在这个一般的思想领域中,区分“实际是什么”和“应该是什么”既重要,又特别难以正确维护。例如,当卢梭指责格劳秀斯(似乎也暗示了霍布斯)“通过事实确立权利”时,他确实有一点值得考虑。卢梭于是刻意地把他自己的社会规范理论建立在别的东西之上,而不是仅仅建立在“对过去滥用行为的记录”之上,即使在天才的洞察力下,他确实找到了一种关于社会起源的描述,尽管不可否认这是一种部分幻想,但在阐述他自己的观点方面很重要然而,正如麦克艾弗教授所指出的那样,批评家自己也犯了一个错误,就像他所批评的那样,他让自己的视野被国家明显的现状所限制,以至于没有看到一个更广泛的、如果不那么明显的关系模式——麦克艾弗用这个词来形容它
{"title":"An Ethical Definition of Community","authors":"J. A. Clark","doi":"10.1086/intejethi.47.2.2989331","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1086/intejethi.47.2.2989331","url":null,"abstract":"T, THE classical iterature of the sciences of society very readily illustrates the proposition that in this general field of thought a distinction between what actually is and what ought to be is both important and peculiarly difficult to maintain correctly. For example, Rousseau surely had a point deserving consideration when he accused Grotius (and by implication, it seems, Hobbes) of \"establishing right by fact. 12 Rousseau then sought quite deliberately to base his own normative theory of society upon something else than any mere \"record of past abuses,\" even if, with the insight of genius, he did find an account of social origins, though admittedly a partially fanciful one, important in the exposition of his own views.3 And yet, as Professor MacIver has argued, the critic himself committed an error not unlike the one he had criticized when he allowed his own vision to be circumscribed by the conspicuous actuality of the state to the extent of failing to see a wider, if less obvious, pattern of relationships-to which MacIver applies the term","PeriodicalId":346392,"journal":{"name":"The International Journal of Ethics","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1937-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"121740160","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Fatalism, Determinism, and Indeterminism 宿命论,决定论和非决定论
Pub Date : 1937-01-01 DOI: 10.1086/intejethi.47.2.2989337
N. P. Stallknecht
W H rHILE agreeing with the very reasonable central thesis of Mrs. Langer's recent article "On a Fallacy in Scientific Fatalism" (International Journal of Ethics, July, I936) I feel that her account of determinism hardly does justice to the schools of thought that oppose this doctrine. I admit straightaway that the determinism which Mrs. Langer and so many modern writers attribute to science as its indispensable presupposition is not to be confused with a fatalism whereby our individual effort is thought to be rendered futile because our future is already determined. It is obvious that in a determined universe such a conclusion itself influences our future and thus, so to speak, suspends its own maxim of the ineffectual nature of our decisions. Only in a fatalism free from the axioms of scientific determinism would such an attitude really be at home. Further, it is true that under determinism certain very important limitations surround the assertion that conscious decisions are predictable. For instance, if a prediction is known to me it may condition my action in an opposite direction. In general, and this even if we consider God as the foreseeing mind, we must admit that the act of foresight cannot itself be a part of the universe to which such foresight refers. Certainly it cannot be causally related to the universe without by its very assertion influencing events in a manner not included in the prediction. (I might comment, however, that in certain determinist theologies God's vision and prevision are considered as one identical supra-temporal act by which the world is maintained not moment by moment but totum simul. Here divine foresight changes nothing or causes no one thing as distinct from another but maintains all things in their total history.) However, I admit that the concept of ideal prevision is no more than a Vaihinger als ob. Nonetheless, I insist that reasonable dislike of determinism is not based upon the distasteful notion that some other mind knows more of our future than we do. Hence the argument that there can be no actually exhaustive prediction of our actions, even if valid, does not remove the real sting of determinism. What the reasonable indeterminist desires to safeguard, if possible, is the real efficacy of consciousness or the self in determining the individual's course of action. Today the really dangerous rival of this doctrine is not fatalism but the very determinism which Mrs. Langer describes as a tenable thesis, neither very radical nor even debatable. This may seem at
虽然我同意兰格夫人最近发表的文章《论科学宿命论中的谬误》(《国际伦理学杂志》,1936年7月)中非常合理的中心论点,但我觉得她对决定论的描述很难公正地对待反对这一学说的思想流派。我坦率地承认,不能把兰格夫人和许多现代作家认为科学不可缺少的前提——决定论——与宿命论相混淆,因为宿命论认为我们的个人努力是徒劳的,因为我们的未来已经决定了。很明显,在一个确定的宇宙中,这样的结论本身影响着我们的未来,因此,可以说,搁置了它自己的格言,即我们的决定是无效的。只有在一种脱离科学决定论公理的宿命论中,这样的态度才真正自在。此外,在决定论下,有意识的决定是可预测的这一论断确实受到了一些非常重要的限制。例如,如果我知道一个预测,它可能会使我的行动朝着相反的方向发展。一般地说,即使我们认为上帝是有预见的精神,我们也必须承认,预见的行为本身并不能成为这种预见所涉及的宇宙的一部分。当然,它不可能与宇宙有因果关系,除非它的断言以一种未包括在预测中的方式影响事件。(然而,我可能会评论说,在某些决定论神学中,上帝的远见和预见被认为是一种相同的超时间行为,通过这种行为,世界不是每时每刻都在维持,而是时时刻刻都在维持。在这里,神的预见不会改变任何事物,也不会使一件事物与另一件事物截然不同,而是在它们的整个历史中维持一切事物。然而,我承认,理想预见的概念只不过是一种维辛格式的偏见。尽管如此,我坚持认为,对决定论的合理厌恶并非基于这样一种令人厌恶的观念,即其他心灵比我们更了解我们的未来。因此,不可能对我们的行为进行真正详尽的预测的论点,即使是有效的,也不能消除决定论的真正刺痛。如果可能的话,理性的不确定性主义者想要维护的是意识或自我在决定个人行为过程中的真正功效。今天,这种学说真正危险的对手不是宿命论,而是兰格夫人所描述的一种站得住脚的论点,既不激进,甚至也不值得争论。这可能看起来
{"title":"Fatalism, Determinism, and Indeterminism","authors":"N. P. Stallknecht","doi":"10.1086/intejethi.47.2.2989337","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1086/intejethi.47.2.2989337","url":null,"abstract":"W H rHILE agreeing with the very reasonable central thesis of Mrs. Langer's recent article \"On a Fallacy in Scientific Fatalism\" (International Journal of Ethics, July, I936) I feel that her account of determinism hardly does justice to the schools of thought that oppose this doctrine. I admit straightaway that the determinism which Mrs. Langer and so many modern writers attribute to science as its indispensable presupposition is not to be confused with a fatalism whereby our individual effort is thought to be rendered futile because our future is already determined. It is obvious that in a determined universe such a conclusion itself influences our future and thus, so to speak, suspends its own maxim of the ineffectual nature of our decisions. Only in a fatalism free from the axioms of scientific determinism would such an attitude really be at home. Further, it is true that under determinism certain very important limitations surround the assertion that conscious decisions are predictable. For instance, if a prediction is known to me it may condition my action in an opposite direction. In general, and this even if we consider God as the foreseeing mind, we must admit that the act of foresight cannot itself be a part of the universe to which such foresight refers. Certainly it cannot be causally related to the universe without by its very assertion influencing events in a manner not included in the prediction. (I might comment, however, that in certain determinist theologies God's vision and prevision are considered as one identical supra-temporal act by which the world is maintained not moment by moment but totum simul. Here divine foresight changes nothing or causes no one thing as distinct from another but maintains all things in their total history.) However, I admit that the concept of ideal prevision is no more than a Vaihinger als ob. Nonetheless, I insist that reasonable dislike of determinism is not based upon the distasteful notion that some other mind knows more of our future than we do. Hence the argument that there can be no actually exhaustive prediction of our actions, even if valid, does not remove the real sting of determinism. What the reasonable indeterminist desires to safeguard, if possible, is the real efficacy of consciousness or the self in determining the individual's course of action. Today the really dangerous rival of this doctrine is not fatalism but the very determinism which Mrs. Langer describes as a tenable thesis, neither very radical nor even debatable. This may seem at","PeriodicalId":346392,"journal":{"name":"The International Journal of Ethics","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1937-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"134271410","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Socratic Justice 苏格拉底的审判
Pub Date : 1937-01-01 DOI: 10.1086/intejethi.47.2.2989334
G. Whitby
OR centuries sociologists have drawn inspiration from Plato's Republic. Of the two minds represented in the work-Plato's, and that of his teacher, Socrates-it is the tutor's which makes the more fundamental and penetrating contribution to social science. It is popularly conceived that Socrates, like the enfant terrible, had a habit of asking awkward questions, and is to be patronized as an early seeker after truth, but that Plato was the man with the constructive ideas. Grote, in his great work, Plato and the Other Companions of Socrates, brings his superb scholarship to the task of proving that, in general, Socrates did not enlighten, but merely puzzled, and that even if he had a consistent ethical doctine it was never stated. It is true, indeed, that Socrates is unable to draw the dialogue of the Lysis to a satisfactory conclusion through failing to see the ambiguity in his loose use of the terms "because of" and "for the sake of,"' but where is the philosopher who is immune from occasional logical error? In his masterly volume on Plato,2 Professor A. E. Taylor, referring to the Lysis and the Parmenides, writes, "In neither case need we suppose that Plato's real intention is to leave us merely befogged." This can readily be granted, but the plain fact would seem to be, in the instance of the Lysis at least, that Socrates, whose name should be read in preference to Plato's, was himself befogged-by his own terminology; and Professor Taylor's ingenious though somewhat labored attempt to bring order out
几个世纪以来,社会学家一直从柏拉图的《理想国》中汲取灵感。在作品中所代表的两种思想中,柏拉图的思想和他的老师苏格拉底的思想,导师的思想对社会科学作出了更根本、更深刻的贡献。人们普遍认为,苏格拉底和那个可怕的孩子一样,也有问一些令人尴尬的问题的习惯,所以他被尊称为一个早期的真理追求者,而柏拉图则是一个具有建设性思想的人。格罗特在他的巨著《柏拉图与苏格拉底的其他同伴》中,用他高超的学识来证明,总的来说,苏格拉底并没有启蒙,而只是迷惑,即使他有一个一贯的伦理教义,也从来没有说出来。的确,苏格拉底无法在《解》的对话中得出一个令人满意的结论,因为他没有看到他松散地使用“因为”和“为了”这两个词的模糊性,但哪里有哲学家能免于偶尔的逻辑错误呢?泰勒(A. E. Taylor)教授在他那本关于柏拉图的巨著中,在提到《解》和《巴门尼德》时写道:“在这两种情况下,我们都不必认为柏拉图的真正意图只是让我们迷惑不解。”这是很容易承认的,但至少就《解》的例子来说,显而易见的事实似乎是,苏格拉底的名字比柏拉图的名字更容易读,但他自己却被他自己的术语所迷惑;以及泰勒教授为恢复秩序所做的巧妙尝试,尽管有些费力
{"title":"Socratic Justice","authors":"G. Whitby","doi":"10.1086/intejethi.47.2.2989334","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1086/intejethi.47.2.2989334","url":null,"abstract":"OR centuries sociologists have drawn inspiration from Plato's Republic. Of the two minds represented in the work-Plato's, and that of his teacher, Socrates-it is the tutor's which makes the more fundamental and penetrating contribution to social science. It is popularly conceived that Socrates, like the enfant terrible, had a habit of asking awkward questions, and is to be patronized as an early seeker after truth, but that Plato was the man with the constructive ideas. Grote, in his great work, Plato and the Other Companions of Socrates, brings his superb scholarship to the task of proving that, in general, Socrates did not enlighten, but merely puzzled, and that even if he had a consistent ethical doctine it was never stated. It is true, indeed, that Socrates is unable to draw the dialogue of the Lysis to a satisfactory conclusion through failing to see the ambiguity in his loose use of the terms \"because of\" and \"for the sake of,\"' but where is the philosopher who is immune from occasional logical error? In his masterly volume on Plato,2 Professor A. E. Taylor, referring to the Lysis and the Parmenides, writes, \"In neither case need we suppose that Plato's real intention is to leave us merely befogged.\" This can readily be granted, but the plain fact would seem to be, in the instance of the Lysis at least, that Socrates, whose name should be read in preference to Plato's, was himself befogged-by his own terminology; and Professor Taylor's ingenious though somewhat labored attempt to bring order out","PeriodicalId":346392,"journal":{"name":"The International Journal of Ethics","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1937-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"129598774","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Relation Between Ethics and Political Science 伦理学与政治学的关系
Pub Date : 1937-01-01 DOI: 10.1086/intejethi.47.2.2989332
C. Perry
I T IS easier to state briefly in simple words the relation between ethics and political science than it is to make clear to one's self or others what is involved in the relation. The relation, in large outline, is not difficult to discover. Political science is the study of what ought to be. It is a normative science, if a linking of the terms "normative" and "science" is permissible. Whether or not it is a science, political theory is a study of norms, and it is also to a considerable extent an art of constructing and reconstructing norms. At this point we need not pause to consider whether political theory is a science or an art or a mixture of both. The important fact is that the material with which political theory deals is norms or oughts or ideals. Ethics, on the contrary, is a description of what is or what exists. It is, in other words, a descriptive science. It does not attempt, to be sure, to give a complete description of what exists, but aims rather at describing certain aspects of existence, or at describing existence from a certain point of view. What aspects of existence are described in ethics will be indicated presently. The immediate point to be noticed is that ethics as description of existence contrasts with political theory, which is a study of what ought to be rather than of what is. This much about ethics and political science lies on the surface for anyone to see; but when one attempts to see below the surface one encounters difficulties. "Norms" and "existence" are words, and one might even say that they are metaphysical abstractions. The plain man is exceedingly fond of metaphysical abstractions, and I am not unaware of their value. If we did not use them freely to simplify the complexities of the world,
用简单的语言简单地陈述伦理和政治科学之间的关系比向自己或他人明确这一关系所涉及的内容要容易得多。大体说来,这种关系不难发现。政治学研究的是“应该是什么”。如果允许将“规范性”和“科学”这两个术语联系起来,它就是一门规范性科学。无论它是否是一门科学,政治理论都是对规范的研究,在相当大的程度上,它也是一门建构和重建规范的艺术。在这一点上,我们不需要停下来考虑政治理论是科学还是艺术,还是两者兼而有之。重要的事实是,政治理论所处理的材料是规范、应该或理想。相反,伦理学是对存在或存在之物的描述。换句话说,它是一门描述科学。当然,它并不试图对存在的东西给出一个完整的描述,而是旨在描述存在的某些方面,或者从某种观点来描述存在。在伦理学中描述了存在的哪些方面,我们将在下面说明。首先要注意的是,伦理学作为对存在的描述,与政治理论形成了对比,政治理论研究的是应该是什么,而不是现在是什么。关于伦理和政治科学的很多内容都是表面上的,任何人都可以看到;但是,当一个人试图看到表面下的东西时,就会遇到困难。“规范”和“存在”都是词语,甚至可以说它们是形而上的抽象。普通人特别喜欢形而上的抽象概念,我并非不知道它们的价值。如果我们不自由地使用它们来简化世界的复杂性,
{"title":"The Relation Between Ethics and Political Science","authors":"C. Perry","doi":"10.1086/intejethi.47.2.2989332","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1086/intejethi.47.2.2989332","url":null,"abstract":"I T IS easier to state briefly in simple words the relation between ethics and political science than it is to make clear to one's self or others what is involved in the relation. The relation, in large outline, is not difficult to discover. Political science is the study of what ought to be. It is a normative science, if a linking of the terms \"normative\" and \"science\" is permissible. Whether or not it is a science, political theory is a study of norms, and it is also to a considerable extent an art of constructing and reconstructing norms. At this point we need not pause to consider whether political theory is a science or an art or a mixture of both. The important fact is that the material with which political theory deals is norms or oughts or ideals. Ethics, on the contrary, is a description of what is or what exists. It is, in other words, a descriptive science. It does not attempt, to be sure, to give a complete description of what exists, but aims rather at describing certain aspects of existence, or at describing existence from a certain point of view. What aspects of existence are described in ethics will be indicated presently. The immediate point to be noticed is that ethics as description of existence contrasts with political theory, which is a study of what ought to be rather than of what is. This much about ethics and political science lies on the surface for anyone to see; but when one attempts to see below the surface one encounters difficulties. \"Norms\" and \"existence\" are words, and one might even say that they are metaphysical abstractions. The plain man is exceedingly fond of metaphysical abstractions, and I am not unaware of their value. If we did not use them freely to simplify the complexities of the world,","PeriodicalId":346392,"journal":{"name":"The International Journal of Ethics","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1937-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"132013135","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 3
Coherence Theory of Goodness 善的连贯说
Pub Date : 1936-10-01 DOI: 10.1086/intejethi.47.1.2989246
M. Konvitz
M t } -ORAL goodness is distinctively human, belongs to conduct as it issues from will and is social."' This passage introduces us at once to the leading notions in Alexander's moral theory: (i) that morality is an affair of motives or will and (2) that it is in essence social. It has been supposed that goodness belongs to the will in itself as a mere mental function. But this is erroneous. The will which is the subject matter of the science of ethics is not the isolated will but the will in its interrelation with other wills. And the will becomes the subject of moral judgment because of its concern with objects which exist apart from it and are contemplated by minds in common. Minds can judge each other as good or bad only as directed upon these objects. I can judge you to be doing right or wrong only so far as I see you willing an object which I approve or condemn. It is not your will I approve merely as a mental process; what I approve is your will for temperate drinking or preservation of property. There is no such thing as inner morality, if it is thought of as independent of what is willed.2
口头的善是人类特有的,属于行为,因为它来源于意志,是社会性的。这段话立刻向我们介绍了亚历山大道德理论中的主要概念:(1)道德是动机或意志的事情;(2)道德本质上是社会的。人们一直认为,善属于意志本身,只是一种精神功能。但这是错误的。作为伦理学研究对象的意志不是孤立的意志,而是与其他意志相互联系的意志。意志之所以成为道德判断的主体,是因为它关注的对象与意志无关,却被共同的心灵所思考。心灵只能根据这些对象来判断对方的好坏。只有当我看到你愿意做一件我赞成或谴责的事情时,我才能判断你做得对或错。我赞成的不是你的意志仅仅是一种心理过程;我赞成的是你节制饮酒或保护财产的意愿。如果认为内在道德独立于意志之外,就不存在这种东西
{"title":"Coherence Theory of Goodness","authors":"M. Konvitz","doi":"10.1086/intejethi.47.1.2989246","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1086/intejethi.47.1.2989246","url":null,"abstract":"M t } -ORAL goodness is distinctively human, belongs to conduct as it issues from will and is social.\"' This passage introduces us at once to the leading notions in Alexander's moral theory: (i) that morality is an affair of motives or will and (2) that it is in essence social. It has been supposed that goodness belongs to the will in itself as a mere mental function. But this is erroneous. The will which is the subject matter of the science of ethics is not the isolated will but the will in its interrelation with other wills. And the will becomes the subject of moral judgment because of its concern with objects which exist apart from it and are contemplated by minds in common. Minds can judge each other as good or bad only as directed upon these objects. I can judge you to be doing right or wrong only so far as I see you willing an object which I approve or condemn. It is not your will I approve merely as a mental process; what I approve is your will for temperate drinking or preservation of property. There is no such thing as inner morality, if it is thought of as independent of what is willed.2","PeriodicalId":346392,"journal":{"name":"The International Journal of Ethics","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1936-10-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"131577476","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
The International Journal of Ethics
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1