首页 > 最新文献

The International Journal of Ethics最新文献

英文 中文
The Philosophy of Aristotle and the Hellenic-Macedonian Policy 亚里士多德哲学与希腊-马其顿政策
Pub Date : 1937-10-01 DOI: 10.1086/intejethi.48.1.2989300
H. Kelsen
I -O F ALL the activities of the mind on which the Aristotelian philosophy has exercised its influence throughout the last two thousand years, on none has the teaching of the Stagira sage acted so directly and so decisively as on ethical and political theory-an influence still apparent at the present day. The almost divine authority which Aristotle enjoyed in the sphere of the natural sciences has long since disappeared; his logic, once admired as the emanation of absolute truth, has been deposed, though only a few generations ago, from its hitherto commanding position. But the profound respect accorded to his Ethics and Politics remains undiminished. Their influence on the thought of our time can scarcely be overestimated. Modern scientific treatments of the problems of a moral world-order and of a juridical state community still, in very great measure, betray the stamp of the Aristotelian system. But in that system Aristotle's Ethics and Politics are essentially connected with his Metaphysics." And thus it is the Metaphysics which appears as the foundation of the moral system of values, whether these values be knowingly accepted in
在过去两千年中,亚里士多德哲学对所有的精神活动都产生了影响,但没有哪一个像在伦理和政治理论上那样直接而决定性地受到了斯塔基拉圣人的教诲——这种影响在今天仍然很明显。亚里士多德在自然科学领域所享有的近乎神圣的权威早已消失;他的逻辑,曾经被推崇为绝对真理的流露,虽然仅仅在几代人之前,已经从其迄今为止的统治地位上被推翻了。但是,人们对他的《伦理学与政治学》的崇敬之情并未减弱。他们对我们这个时代思想的影响怎么估计也不为过。现代科学对道德世界秩序和法律国家共同体问题的处理,在很大程度上仍然暴露出亚里士多德体系的印记。但在这个体系中,亚里士多德的《伦理学与政治学》本质上与他的《形而上学》联系在一起因此,形而上学表现为道德价值体系的基础,不管这些价值是否被有意地接受
{"title":"The Philosophy of Aristotle and the Hellenic-Macedonian Policy","authors":"H. Kelsen","doi":"10.1086/intejethi.48.1.2989300","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1086/intejethi.48.1.2989300","url":null,"abstract":"I -O F ALL the activities of the mind on which the Aristotelian philosophy has exercised its influence throughout the last two thousand years, on none has the teaching of the Stagira sage acted so directly and so decisively as on ethical and political theory-an influence still apparent at the present day. The almost divine authority which Aristotle enjoyed in the sphere of the natural sciences has long since disappeared; his logic, once admired as the emanation of absolute truth, has been deposed, though only a few generations ago, from its hitherto commanding position. But the profound respect accorded to his Ethics and Politics remains undiminished. Their influence on the thought of our time can scarcely be overestimated. Modern scientific treatments of the problems of a moral world-order and of a juridical state community still, in very great measure, betray the stamp of the Aristotelian system. But in that system Aristotle's Ethics and Politics are essentially connected with his Metaphysics.\" And thus it is the Metaphysics which appears as the foundation of the moral system of values, whether these values be knowingly accepted in","PeriodicalId":346392,"journal":{"name":"The International Journal of Ethics","volume":"1 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1937-10-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"130124659","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 36
A Legislator Looks at Legislation 立法者看立法
Pub Date : 1937-10-01 DOI: 10.1086/intejethi.48.1.2989301
T. V. Smith, G. C. Routt
N i ' OT since Bentham's Principles of Morals and Legislation has there appeared in English a study of legislation so pretentious as this four-volume work of the Honorable Robert Luce. Yet this comparison might well be odious to both authors. Bentham was concerned, as the title of his work shows, almost exclusively with principles: not only of legislation but also, if not indeed primarily, of morals. His work was put inside a single volume,was pungently even dogmatically written, was sectarian in point of view (hedonic), and was done almost deductively from beginning to end. In a word, Bentham's work was a philosophy of legislation. Mr. Luce's work is not a philosophy but a manual (though published under the title of "Science of Legislation"). True, it is loosejointed in scope (four large volumes), it is free-associational in method, it is eclectic in outlook, it is anecdotal in its inditement But it remains a manual-a manual deferential to history and tolerant of variety but preoccupied primarily with practice. (Would that every author furnished his manual with as complete an index as each volume here has!). Unlike Bentham's work, this comprehensive discussion is focused on the legislative arena: its counsels are redolent of debate (seeing I Four volumes by Robert Luce. Boston and New York: Houghton Miffin Co. Reference is made to the volumes in the following order: I. Legislative Procedure: Parliamentary Practices and the Course of Business in the Framing of Statutes. I922. Pp. vi+628. $5.00. II. Legislative Assemblies: Their Framework, Make-up, Character, Characteristics, Habits, and Manners. I924. Pp. vi+69i. $6.oo. III. Legislative Principles: The History and Theory of Lawmaking by Representative Government. I930. Pp. vi+667. $6.oo. IV. Legislative Problems: Development, Status, and Trend of the Treatment and Exercise of Lawmaking Powers. I935. Pp. vi+762. $6.oo.
自从边沁的《道德与立法原则》以来,英语中还没有出现过像尊敬的罗伯特·卢斯的这部四卷本的立法研究如此自命不凡的著作。然而,这种比较可能会让两位作者都感到厌恶。边沁所关注的,正如他著作的标题所示,几乎完全是原则:不仅是立法原则,而且,如果不是主要原则,也是道德原则。他的作品被放在一卷书里,写得辛辣甚至武断,观点宗派(享乐主义),从头到尾几乎都是演绎的。总之,边沁的著作是一种立法哲学。卢斯先生的著作不是哲学,而是一本手册(尽管以“立法科学”的名义出版)。的确,它在范围上是松散的(四卷),在方法上是自由结合的,在观点上是折衷的,在写作上是轶事的,但它仍然是一本手册——一本尊重历史,容忍多样性,但主要关注实践的手册。(但愿每一位作者在他的手册里都有像这里的每一卷一样完整的索引!)与边沁的著作不同,这本全面的讨论集中在立法领域:它的建议充满了辩论的味道(参见罗伯特·卢斯的四卷书)。波士顿和纽约:霍顿米芬公司。参考这些卷按以下顺序:1 .立法程序:制定法规中的议会实践和业务过程。I922。Pp. vi + 628。5.00美元。2立法会议:它们的框架、组成、特征、特点、习惯和礼仪。I924。我Pp. vi + 69。oo 6.美元。3立法原则:代议制政府立法的历史与理论。I930。Pp. vi + 667。oo 6.美元。四、立法问题:立法权待遇与行使的发展、现状与趋势。I935。Pp. vi + 762。oo 6.美元。
{"title":"A Legislator Looks at Legislation","authors":"T. V. Smith, G. C. Routt","doi":"10.1086/intejethi.48.1.2989301","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1086/intejethi.48.1.2989301","url":null,"abstract":"N i ' OT since Bentham's Principles of Morals and Legislation has there appeared in English a study of legislation so pretentious as this four-volume work of the Honorable Robert Luce. Yet this comparison might well be odious to both authors. Bentham was concerned, as the title of his work shows, almost exclusively with principles: not only of legislation but also, if not indeed primarily, of morals. His work was put inside a single volume,was pungently even dogmatically written, was sectarian in point of view (hedonic), and was done almost deductively from beginning to end. In a word, Bentham's work was a philosophy of legislation. Mr. Luce's work is not a philosophy but a manual (though published under the title of \"Science of Legislation\"). True, it is loosejointed in scope (four large volumes), it is free-associational in method, it is eclectic in outlook, it is anecdotal in its inditement But it remains a manual-a manual deferential to history and tolerant of variety but preoccupied primarily with practice. (Would that every author furnished his manual with as complete an index as each volume here has!). Unlike Bentham's work, this comprehensive discussion is focused on the legislative arena: its counsels are redolent of debate (seeing I Four volumes by Robert Luce. Boston and New York: Houghton Miffin Co. Reference is made to the volumes in the following order: I. Legislative Procedure: Parliamentary Practices and the Course of Business in the Framing of Statutes. I922. Pp. vi+628. $5.00. II. Legislative Assemblies: Their Framework, Make-up, Character, Characteristics, Habits, and Manners. I924. Pp. vi+69i. $6.oo. III. Legislative Principles: The History and Theory of Lawmaking by Representative Government. I930. Pp. vi+667. $6.oo. IV. Legislative Problems: Development, Status, and Trend of the Treatment and Exercise of Lawmaking Powers. I935. Pp. vi+762. $6.oo.","PeriodicalId":346392,"journal":{"name":"The International Journal of Ethics","volume":"38 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1937-10-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"133185287","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Shorter Notices 较短的通知
Pub Date : 1937-10-01 DOI: 10.1086/intejethi.48.1.2989312
D. Emmet, Roman Catholicism
leianism as "vicious intellectualism" is clearly unfair. Bradley and Bergson both criticize the categories of science as partial viewpoints and reject the view that the absolute is a logical construction. Both look for a means of apprehending a reality which is an individual unity and includes feeling. So Bergson's "intuition" is fruitfully compared with Bradley's "higher immediacy." Bergson comes out of the comparison best in Mr. Loomba's eyes. This is partly because of his deeper appreciation of life and growth. Bradley's absolute became a static "block universe." But this, Mr. Loomba interestingly urges, is not a necessary consequence of Bradley's metaphysical attitude, so much as conditioned by the philosophic tradition in which he stood. His absolute is really the immediate collective experience of the multiplicity of appearances, which in effect he considers as an ideal and so renders static. So much we may grant on Bergson's side. But on the other counts, unlike Mr. Loomba, we are inclined to give higher marks to Bradley. Bergson believes that his "intuition" can be completely realized-that we can achieve a form of thought which dispenses altogether with symbols. Bradley is to the end more sceptical-we can have partial experience of such Scientia intuitive, but in its fulness it is o068 Kr'frov TOP
莱伊主义被称为“邪恶的理智主义”显然是不公平的。布拉德利和柏格森都批评科学的范畴是片面的观点,并反对绝对是一种逻辑结构的观点。两者都在寻找一种理解现实的方法,现实是一个个体的统一体,包括感觉。因此,柏格森的“直觉”与布拉德利的“更高的即时性”相比是卓有成效的。在隆巴看来,柏格森最适合这种比较。这部分是因为他对生活和成长有了更深刻的理解。布拉德利的绝对变成了一个静态的“块宇宙”。但有趣的是,隆巴先生认为,这并不是布拉德利形而上学态度的必然结果,而是他所处的哲学传统所制约的结果。他的绝对实际上是表象多样性的直接集体经验,实际上他认为这是一种理想,因此是静态的。这么多我们都同意柏格森的观点。但在其他方面,不像隆巴先生,我们倾向于给布拉德利更高的分数。柏格森相信他的“直觉”是可以完全实现的——我们可以获得一种完全不需要符号的思维形式。布莱德雷到最后更持怀疑态度——我们可以有这种科学直觉的部分经验,但就其全部而言,它是来自TOP的
{"title":"Shorter Notices","authors":"D. Emmet, Roman Catholicism","doi":"10.1086/intejethi.48.1.2989312","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1086/intejethi.48.1.2989312","url":null,"abstract":"leianism as \"vicious intellectualism\" is clearly unfair. Bradley and Bergson both criticize the categories of science as partial viewpoints and reject the view that the absolute is a logical construction. Both look for a means of apprehending a reality which is an individual unity and includes feeling. So Bergson's \"intuition\" is fruitfully compared with Bradley's \"higher immediacy.\" Bergson comes out of the comparison best in Mr. Loomba's eyes. This is partly because of his deeper appreciation of life and growth. Bradley's absolute became a static \"block universe.\" But this, Mr. Loomba interestingly urges, is not a necessary consequence of Bradley's metaphysical attitude, so much as conditioned by the philosophic tradition in which he stood. His absolute is really the immediate collective experience of the multiplicity of appearances, which in effect he considers as an ideal and so renders static. So much we may grant on Bergson's side. But on the other counts, unlike Mr. Loomba, we are inclined to give higher marks to Bradley. Bergson believes that his \"intuition\" can be completely realized-that we can achieve a form of thought which dispenses altogether with symbols. Bradley is to the end more sceptical-we can have partial experience of such Scientia intuitive, but in its fulness it is o068 Kr'frov TOP","PeriodicalId":346392,"journal":{"name":"The International Journal of Ethics","volume":"16 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1937-10-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"117160968","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
An Analysis of Jewish Culture 犹太文化分析
Pub Date : 1937-07-01 DOI: 10.1086/intejethi.47.4.2989368
T H E psychology of cultural antipathies, often erroneously miscalled racial prejudices, while subtle, is not difficult to understand once the true nature of culture and its relationship to personality is fully grasped. The almost infinite number of behavior patterns which the human organism is capable of forming under the guidance of a rich cultural background is only less amazing than the variety of organization which these patterns may assume. Thus, although we recognize as fellow-humans the products of strange cultures, for we recognize familiar behavior patterns in them, nevertheless they seem slightly out of focus to us because their organization is strange. We do not feel completely at home with members of other cultures, and this is the basic psychological substratum for our fears and antipathies. The old idea that personality was something inherent within the organism which was simply educed by outer surroundings has given way, under the impact of the analyses of men like Baldwin, Cooley, Dewey, Mead, and Bernard, to a more socialized theory in which personality is seen to lie to a great degree in our responses to the people and things about us. According to this view, personality consists in a complex set of relationships between the organism and its setting. The people and things which surround us contribute as much to our personalities as we do, and any violent truncation of these outer
文化反感的心理,经常被错误地称为种族偏见,虽然微妙,但一旦文化的真正本质及其与个性的关系被充分掌握,就不难理解。在丰富的文化背景的指导下,人类有机体能够形成的几乎无穷无尽的行为模式,与这些模式可能呈现的各种组织形式相比,只是不那么令人惊讶。因此,尽管我们把陌生文化的产物视为人类同胞,因为我们在他们身上发现了熟悉的行为模式,然而,他们似乎有点偏离了我们的焦点,因为他们的组织是奇怪的。我们和其他文化的人在一起感到不自在,这是我们恐惧和反感的基本心理基础。在鲍德温、库利、杜威、米德和伯纳德等人的分析影响下,认为人格是机体内固有的东西,只是由外部环境所影响的旧观点已经让位于一种更加社会化的理论,在这种理论中,人格在很大程度上体现在我们对周围人和事的反应中。根据这一观点,人格由机体与其环境之间的一系列复杂关系构成。我们周围的人和事和我们一样,对我们的个性也有很大的贡献,任何对这些外在因素的粗暴破坏
{"title":"An Analysis of Jewish Culture","authors":"","doi":"10.1086/intejethi.47.4.2989368","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1086/intejethi.47.4.2989368","url":null,"abstract":"T H E psychology of cultural antipathies, often erroneously miscalled racial prejudices, while subtle, is not difficult to understand once the true nature of culture and its relationship to personality is fully grasped. The almost infinite number of behavior patterns which the human organism is capable of forming under the guidance of a rich cultural background is only less amazing than the variety of organization which these patterns may assume. Thus, although we recognize as fellow-humans the products of strange cultures, for we recognize familiar behavior patterns in them, nevertheless they seem slightly out of focus to us because their organization is strange. We do not feel completely at home with members of other cultures, and this is the basic psychological substratum for our fears and antipathies. The old idea that personality was something inherent within the organism which was simply educed by outer surroundings has given way, under the impact of the analyses of men like Baldwin, Cooley, Dewey, Mead, and Bernard, to a more socialized theory in which personality is seen to lie to a great degree in our responses to the people and things about us. According to this view, personality consists in a complex set of relationships between the organism and its setting. The people and things which surround us contribute as much to our personalities as we do, and any violent truncation of these outer","PeriodicalId":346392,"journal":{"name":"The International Journal of Ethics","volume":"56 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1937-07-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"130772945","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Metaphors and Metaphysics 隐喻与形而上学
Pub Date : 1937-07-01 DOI: 10.1086/intejethi.47.4.2989370
E. W. Strong
5 T WH ETHER in sympathy or antipathy, there are A/1I many philosophers who have been concerned with V Professor Dewey's treatment of metaphysics. For Dewey, the role of philosophy as criticism is a "straight and narrow path." While philosophical discourse partakes of literary discourse, its task is restricted to analysis and evaluation. Not thus restricted are the arts of literary discourse, for, as Dewey writes, "they have a freer office to perform-to perpetuate, enhance and vivify in imagination the natural goods; ." The restriction of philosophy to the task of criticism entails the casting-out of cosmological system-making. Metaphysics is concerned solely with a description of the generic traits of existence. A descriptive naturalism notes and registers, detects and defines, the "inextricable mixture of stability and uncertainty" displayed by events in their histories. Such a metaphysics is a "preliminary outline of the field of criticism, whose chief import is to afford understanding of the necessity and nature of the office of intelligence." The preliminary outline is no ultimate explanation of anything. No theology or superscience is admitted as a legitimate conversion into a cosmological status of those traits that are precious to us. The ontologically descriptive is not followed by the cosmologically prescriptive. Dewey, in his metaphysics, sets before us the conditions of diversity and mutability which challenge men but offers us no cosmic security, guidance, or solace. Philosophy as criticism looks to the derivations, contexts, and references of our beliefs, meanings, and values and recommends intelligence to provide instruments of choice and control.
无论是同情还是反感,有许多哲学家一直关注杜威教授对形而上学的处理。对于杜威来说,哲学作为批判的作用是一条“笔直而狭窄的道路”。哲学话语虽然具有文学话语的部分,但其任务仅限于分析和评价。文学话语的艺术并没有受到这样的限制,因为,正如杜威所写的那样,“它们有更自由的职责去履行——在想象中延续、增强和生动自然之物;把哲学局限于批判的任务,就意味着抛弃了宇宙论的体系建构。形而上学只关心对存在的一般特征的描述。一种描述性的自然主义记录、记录、发现并定义了历史事件所显示的“稳定与不确定性的不可分割的混合”。这样一种形而上学是“批判领域的初步轮廓,其主要意义在于提供对智力职能的必要性和性质的理解”。初步的提纲并不是对任何事情的最终解释。没有神学或超科学被认为是对那些对我们宝贵的特征的合理转换。本体论上的描述并没有遵循宇宙论上的规定。杜威在他的形而上学中,向我们展示了多样性和可变性的条件,这些条件向人类提出了挑战,但却没有给我们提供宇宙的安全、指导或安慰。作为批判的哲学关注我们的信仰、意义和价值观的衍生、背景和参考,并推荐智慧来提供选择和控制的工具。
{"title":"Metaphors and Metaphysics","authors":"E. W. Strong","doi":"10.1086/intejethi.47.4.2989370","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1086/intejethi.47.4.2989370","url":null,"abstract":"5 T WH ETHER in sympathy or antipathy, there are A/1I many philosophers who have been concerned with V Professor Dewey's treatment of metaphysics. For Dewey, the role of philosophy as criticism is a \"straight and narrow path.\" While philosophical discourse partakes of literary discourse, its task is restricted to analysis and evaluation. Not thus restricted are the arts of literary discourse, for, as Dewey writes, \"they have a freer office to perform-to perpetuate, enhance and vivify in imagination the natural goods; .\" The restriction of philosophy to the task of criticism entails the casting-out of cosmological system-making. Metaphysics is concerned solely with a description of the generic traits of existence. A descriptive naturalism notes and registers, detects and defines, the \"inextricable mixture of stability and uncertainty\" displayed by events in their histories. Such a metaphysics is a \"preliminary outline of the field of criticism, whose chief import is to afford understanding of the necessity and nature of the office of intelligence.\" The preliminary outline is no ultimate explanation of anything. No theology or superscience is admitted as a legitimate conversion into a cosmological status of those traits that are precious to us. The ontologically descriptive is not followed by the cosmologically prescriptive. Dewey, in his metaphysics, sets before us the conditions of diversity and mutability which challenge men but offers us no cosmic security, guidance, or solace. Philosophy as criticism looks to the derivations, contexts, and references of our beliefs, meanings, and values and recommends intelligence to provide instruments of choice and control.","PeriodicalId":346392,"journal":{"name":"The International Journal of Ethics","volume":"19 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1937-07-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"133520601","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 5
The If's and Ought's of Ethics. Cecil de Boer 伦理学的“如果”和“应该”。塞西尔·德布尔
Pub Date : 1937-07-01 DOI: 10.1086/INTEJETHI.47.4.2989379
H. Larrabee
{"title":"The If's and Ought's of Ethics. Cecil de Boer","authors":"H. Larrabee","doi":"10.1086/INTEJETHI.47.4.2989379","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1086/INTEJETHI.47.4.2989379","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":346392,"journal":{"name":"The International Journal of Ethics","volume":"54 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1937-07-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"128969387","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Sport 体育运动
Pub Date : 1937-07-01 DOI: 10.1086/intejethi.47.4.2989371
Percy Hughes
AS WE turn the pages of a well-planned newspaper we see that in modern life certain activities are so segregated as to achieve some measure of autotelic and autonomous organization: for instance, medicine, religion, industry, art, science, government, education, sport, etc. In democratic societies these segregations are more complete, at least in the negative sense that no external influence presumes in general to dictate. "Sport," for example, goes its way with but sporadic interference from medicine, education, religion, or government. But at present, within each such field of segregation, one finds little positive insight into the whole range of the activities that are involved, and of the several distinct, indispensable factors that enter into the situation, of which each calls for development peculiar to itself. So we see that in religion, beside the religion of the "churches," we must recognize that secular, political, and theocratic religion all enter into every concrete situation where a religious problem arises.' Failure to recognize this essential manifoldness of the religious problem gives rise to moralizing and contention rather than to fresh vision and inspired achievement. Similarly in matters of sport we see a round condemnation of procedures in one phase of sport in terms of criteria applicable only to another; while there is lacking such broad and discriminating cultivation of sport in all its phases as most diversifies, invigorates, and gladdens life. Surveys of each such field of segregated activities are one chief function of ethical study, so that in making a practical decision we may do so with some vision of the entire field within which that decision will produce effects. All such segregations do indeed interact, and a broader survey will bring this interaction into clearer view. First, however, we need more adequate surveys than we now have of each segregation, for the purpose of winning for every indispensable factor therein due recognition and full development. In every such segregation we must first appreciate that factor of feeling
当我们翻阅一份精心策划的报纸时,我们会看到,在现代生活中,某些活动是如此分离,以至于达到了某种程度上的自动和自主的组织:例如,医学、宗教、工业、艺术、科学、政府、教育、体育等。在民主社会中,这种隔离更为彻底,至少从消极的意义上说,没有外部影响可以普遍支配。例如,“体育运动”的发展只受到医学、教育、宗教或政府的零星干预。但目前,在每一个这样的隔离领域中,人们发现对所涉及的活动的整个范围,以及对进入这种情况的几个独特的、不可或缺的因素,几乎没有积极的见解,每个因素都需要自己特有的发展。因此,我们看到,在宗教方面,除了“教会”的宗教之外,我们必须承认,世俗宗教、政治宗教和神权宗教都进入到每一个出现宗教问题的具体情况中。如果不能认识到宗教问题的这种本质的多样性,就会产生道德说教和争论,而不是产生新的视野和鼓舞人心的成就。同样地,在体育运动中,我们看到在体育运动的一个阶段中,人们用只适用于另一个阶段的标准来谴责程序;虽然在各个阶段都缺乏广泛和有区别的体育培养,因为大多数体育使生活多样化,充满活力和快乐。对每一个这样的隔离活动领域进行调查是伦理研究的一个主要功能,因此,在做出实际决定时,我们可以对该决定将在其中产生影响的整个领域有所了解。所有这些种族隔离确实相互作用,更广泛的调查将使这种相互作用更清晰。然而,首先,我们需要比现在对每一种种族隔离进行更充分的调查,以便使其中每一个不可或缺的因素得到应有的承认和充分的发展。在每一种这样的隔离中,我们必须首先认识到感情的因素
{"title":"Sport","authors":"Percy Hughes","doi":"10.1086/intejethi.47.4.2989371","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1086/intejethi.47.4.2989371","url":null,"abstract":"AS WE turn the pages of a well-planned newspaper we see that in modern life certain activities are so segregated as to achieve some measure of autotelic and autonomous organization: for instance, medicine, religion, industry, art, science, government, education, sport, etc. In democratic societies these segregations are more complete, at least in the negative sense that no external influence presumes in general to dictate. \"Sport,\" for example, goes its way with but sporadic interference from medicine, education, religion, or government. But at present, within each such field of segregation, one finds little positive insight into the whole range of the activities that are involved, and of the several distinct, indispensable factors that enter into the situation, of which each calls for development peculiar to itself. So we see that in religion, beside the religion of the \"churches,\" we must recognize that secular, political, and theocratic religion all enter into every concrete situation where a religious problem arises.' Failure to recognize this essential manifoldness of the religious problem gives rise to moralizing and contention rather than to fresh vision and inspired achievement. Similarly in matters of sport we see a round condemnation of procedures in one phase of sport in terms of criteria applicable only to another; while there is lacking such broad and discriminating cultivation of sport in all its phases as most diversifies, invigorates, and gladdens life. Surveys of each such field of segregated activities are one chief function of ethical study, so that in making a practical decision we may do so with some vision of the entire field within which that decision will produce effects. All such segregations do indeed interact, and a broader survey will bring this interaction into clearer view. First, however, we need more adequate surveys than we now have of each segregation, for the purpose of winning for every indispensable factor therein due recognition and full development. In every such segregation we must first appreciate that factor of feeling","PeriodicalId":346392,"journal":{"name":"The International Journal of Ethics","volume":"14 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1937-07-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"114419111","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Moral Skepticism and the Way of Escape 道德怀疑主义与逃避之道
Pub Date : 1937-07-01 DOI: 10.1086/intejethi.47.4.2989369
A. E. Avey
S KEPTICISM is the characteristic mark of the thinking of the present age on moral questions. Whatever pretensions are made to the validity of the criticism of human conduct, it still remains that these are pretensions. In practice we find fault with one another, accuse our fellows of living on a low level of existence, and berate the social standards of the day. Yet when we undertake deliberately and seriously to point out the objective principles of conduct which we are presupposing in our judgments, and to demonstrate why they are objective and applicable to the person criticized, we begin to hedge and to compromise, making fatal concession to the skeptic and admitting that after all it is a matter of custom, of personal conviction, or of some other merely individual standard. On the part of the common man there is no more expressive representation of this skepticism than the challenge so often heard in the face of criticism: "That's what you think." If we turn to literary authority, we find the word of Shakespeare: "There's nothing either good or bad but thinking makes it so." Or, if we seek more orthodox authority, we may quote even Paul's liberal advice to the Corinthians: "If one of them that believe not biddeth you to a feast, and ye are disposed to go; whatever is set before you, eat, asking no question for conscience' sake" (I Cor. IO: 27). In the detailed study of the history of morals we have Westermarck's well-known account. And nearer home, from the collaboration of a group of philosophers a few years ago, this statement: To the arguments of the complete moral skeptic, it must be admitted, there can be made no conclusive and irrefutable reply. But neither can
怀疑主义是当代道德问题思想的特征标志。无论对人类行为批评的有效性有何妄自尊大,这些都是妄自尊大。在实践中,我们互相挑剔,指责我们的同伴生活水平低下,痛斥当今的社会标准。然而,当我们有意而认真地指出我们在判断中所预设的客观行为原则,并证明为什么这些原则是客观的,适用于被批评的人时,我们就开始回避和妥协,对怀疑论者作出致命的让步,承认这毕竟是一个习惯问题,个人信念问题,或其他一些仅仅是个人标准的问题。对于普通人来说,没有什么比面对批评时经常听到的挑战更能表达这种怀疑了:“那是你的想法。”如果我们转向文学权威,我们会发现莎士比亚的话:“没有什么是好的或坏的,是思想决定的。”或者,如果我们寻求更正统的权威,我们甚至可以引用保罗对哥林多人的慷慨劝告:“他们中间若有不信的请你们赴席,你们也情愿去;凡摆在你们面前的,你们只管吃,不要为良心的缘故问什么话”(林前15:27)。在对道德历史的详细研究中,我们看到了韦斯特马克著名的叙述。更切题的是,几年前,一群哲学家合作发表了这样一段话:必须承认,对于完全的道德怀疑论者的论点,没有确凿的、无可辩驳的回答。但也不能
{"title":"Moral Skepticism and the Way of Escape","authors":"A. E. Avey","doi":"10.1086/intejethi.47.4.2989369","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1086/intejethi.47.4.2989369","url":null,"abstract":"S KEPTICISM is the characteristic mark of the thinking of the present age on moral questions. Whatever pretensions are made to the validity of the criticism of human conduct, it still remains that these are pretensions. In practice we find fault with one another, accuse our fellows of living on a low level of existence, and berate the social standards of the day. Yet when we undertake deliberately and seriously to point out the objective principles of conduct which we are presupposing in our judgments, and to demonstrate why they are objective and applicable to the person criticized, we begin to hedge and to compromise, making fatal concession to the skeptic and admitting that after all it is a matter of custom, of personal conviction, or of some other merely individual standard. On the part of the common man there is no more expressive representation of this skepticism than the challenge so often heard in the face of criticism: \"That's what you think.\" If we turn to literary authority, we find the word of Shakespeare: \"There's nothing either good or bad but thinking makes it so.\" Or, if we seek more orthodox authority, we may quote even Paul's liberal advice to the Corinthians: \"If one of them that believe not biddeth you to a feast, and ye are disposed to go; whatever is set before you, eat, asking no question for conscience' sake\" (I Cor. IO: 27). In the detailed study of the history of morals we have Westermarck's well-known account. And nearer home, from the collaboration of a group of philosophers a few years ago, this statement: To the arguments of the complete moral skeptic, it must be admitted, there can be made no conclusive and irrefutable reply. But neither can","PeriodicalId":346392,"journal":{"name":"The International Journal of Ethics","volume":"64 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1937-07-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"126748645","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Philosophy and Democracy 哲学与民主
Pub Date : 1937-07-01 DOI: 10.1086/intejethi.47.4.2989367
T. V. Smith
O F THE three great stages for the theater of life, two body forth the distinctively human show. First, however, there is the more elementary behavior of manthe stage of animal urgency. Then there is action guided by ends-the stage of political endeavor. Finally, there is contemplation of ideals or of whatever else-the stage of philosophic wonder and worth. Our present preoccupation is with the political and the philosophic. The lower stage of purely animal behavior is here remarked for perspective and as a reminder that the human spirit has no final immunity from the heats of body and the fumes of earth. The vocation of man advances through political sublimation of animal urgency to contemplation as catharsis for action, political or animal. Without prejudging other means than the natural for this advance, let us focus attention upon man's predicament at its worst to see whether ideal potencies of real promise may not lie
人生的舞台有三个大舞台,其中两个舞台展现了人类的独特之处。然而,首先是人类更基本的行为——动物的紧急状态。然后是目标导向的行动——政治努力阶段。最后,是对理想或其他事物的沉思,这是哲学的奇迹和价值的阶段。我们目前关注的是政治和哲学。纯粹动物行为的低级阶段在此加以说明,并作为一种提醒,即人类的精神对身体的热量和地球的烟雾没有最终的免疫力。人的天职通过动物的急迫性的政治升华而发展到作为行动的宣泄的沉思,无论是政治的还是动物的。在不预先判断这种进步的自然手段之外的其他手段的情况下,让我们把注意力集中在人类最糟糕的困境上,看看真正的希望的理想力量是否可能不存在
{"title":"Philosophy and Democracy","authors":"T. V. Smith","doi":"10.1086/intejethi.47.4.2989367","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1086/intejethi.47.4.2989367","url":null,"abstract":"O F THE three great stages for the theater of life, two body forth the distinctively human show. First, however, there is the more elementary behavior of manthe stage of animal urgency. Then there is action guided by ends-the stage of political endeavor. Finally, there is contemplation of ideals or of whatever else-the stage of philosophic wonder and worth. Our present preoccupation is with the political and the philosophic. The lower stage of purely animal behavior is here remarked for perspective and as a reminder that the human spirit has no final immunity from the heats of body and the fumes of earth. The vocation of man advances through political sublimation of animal urgency to contemplation as catharsis for action, political or animal. Without prejudging other means than the natural for this advance, let us focus attention upon man's predicament at its worst to see whether ideal potencies of real promise may not lie","PeriodicalId":346392,"journal":{"name":"The International Journal of Ethics","volume":"77 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1937-07-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"126583309","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Shorter Notices 较短的通知
Pub Date : 1937-07-01 DOI: 10.1086/intejethi.47.4.2989384
Shorter Notices, Recht Und Sittlichkeit, By Rudolf Laun, Berlin Julius Springer
The author accepts Kant's distinction between being and ought. Law as a science must be either a natural science having nothing to do with duty and ought or a cultural science whose main concerns are judgments of value. The positivistic conception of law is mistaken. For it is impossible to derive right from might, duty from force, ought from must. The final ground of the value judgments of law is discovered in the autonomous experience of a concrete ought. Kant needs to be corrected on two counts: (i) His distinction between a rule of morality as a categorical and a rule of law as a hypothetical imperative needs to be formulated more sharply. (2) An abstract moral law in Kant's sense cannot be discovered anywhere in experience. Kant's hypothetical imperatives are no imperatives at all. They are propositions concerning causal relations. If an imperative expresses an ought it cannot be heteronomous, and if it is heteronomous it cannot express an ought. Consequently, only two attitudes are possible toward positive law. Either the individual approves of it and experiences it as a concrete ought or he disapproves of it and fails to feel its obligatoriness. In the first case the particular law is law (right) in a genuine sense; in the second it is not law but force. Concerning the second point it must be urged in opposition to Kant that the ought of law is always found imbedded in a concrete situation. The individual finds himself face to face with two factors: on the one hand, commands; on the other, group obedience. For he obeys the person issuing the command not in so far as the latter is a private person, but in so far as he represents the judgments of value of the group and of himself. Law in this autonomous sense can never possess universal, but only relatively general, validity. The special concern of a theory of law is the source of law, i.e., the sense of right of the folk. Its chief question is: How far do the heteronomous commands of state, church, and international law agree with the autonomous law of the people? The age-old opposition between the people's law and the jurist's law must gradually be overcome. All heteronomous law must more and more be brought into agreement with the right or the ideal law which is found in the sense of right of humanity. BONNO TAPPER
作者同意康德对存在与应当的区分。法律作为一门科学,要么是一门与责任和义务无关的自然科学,要么是一门主要关注价值判断的文化科学。实证主义的法律观念是错误的。因为不可能从强力中得出权利,从强力中得出责任,从必须中得出应当。法的价值判断的最终根据是在具体应当的自主经验中发现的。康德需要在两个方面加以纠正:(i)他对道德规则作为直言的规则和法律规则作为假设性命令的规则的区分需要更明确地表述。(2)康德意义上的抽象道德法则,在经验中是找不到的。康德的假言命令根本不是命令。它们是关于因果关系的命题。如果一个命令表达了一个“应当”,它就不可能是他律的,如果它是他律的,它就不可能表达一个“应当”。因此,对于成文法只有两种可能的态度。个人要么赞同它,并将其作为一种具体的“应该”来体验,要么不赞同它,并没有感受到它的强制性。在第一种情况下,特定的法律是真正意义上的法律(权利);在第二种情况下,它不是法律,而是武力。关于第二点,我们必须反对康德的观点,即法律的应当性总是隐藏在具体的情况中。个人发现自己面对着两个因素:一方面是命令;另一方面,群体服从。因为他服从发出命令的人,不是因为后者是一个私人,而是因为他代表了群体和他自己的价值判断。这种自主意义上的法律永远不可能具有普遍的效力,而只能具有相对普遍的效力。法律理论特别关注的是法律的渊源,即民间的权利意识。它的主要问题是:国家、教会和国际法的他律命令在多大程度上与人民的自治法律相一致?人民法和法学家法之间由来已久的对立必须逐步克服。一切他律法都必须逐渐与人类权利意义上的权利或理想法律相一致。BONNO攻丝机
{"title":"Shorter Notices","authors":"Shorter Notices, Recht Und Sittlichkeit, By Rudolf Laun, Berlin Julius Springer","doi":"10.1086/intejethi.47.4.2989384","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1086/intejethi.47.4.2989384","url":null,"abstract":"The author accepts Kant's distinction between being and ought. Law as a science must be either a natural science having nothing to do with duty and ought or a cultural science whose main concerns are judgments of value. The positivistic conception of law is mistaken. For it is impossible to derive right from might, duty from force, ought from must. The final ground of the value judgments of law is discovered in the autonomous experience of a concrete ought. Kant needs to be corrected on two counts: (i) His distinction between a rule of morality as a categorical and a rule of law as a hypothetical imperative needs to be formulated more sharply. (2) An abstract moral law in Kant's sense cannot be discovered anywhere in experience. Kant's hypothetical imperatives are no imperatives at all. They are propositions concerning causal relations. If an imperative expresses an ought it cannot be heteronomous, and if it is heteronomous it cannot express an ought. Consequently, only two attitudes are possible toward positive law. Either the individual approves of it and experiences it as a concrete ought or he disapproves of it and fails to feel its obligatoriness. In the first case the particular law is law (right) in a genuine sense; in the second it is not law but force. Concerning the second point it must be urged in opposition to Kant that the ought of law is always found imbedded in a concrete situation. The individual finds himself face to face with two factors: on the one hand, commands; on the other, group obedience. For he obeys the person issuing the command not in so far as the latter is a private person, but in so far as he represents the judgments of value of the group and of himself. Law in this autonomous sense can never possess universal, but only relatively general, validity. The special concern of a theory of law is the source of law, i.e., the sense of right of the folk. Its chief question is: How far do the heteronomous commands of state, church, and international law agree with the autonomous law of the people? The age-old opposition between the people's law and the jurist's law must gradually be overcome. All heteronomous law must more and more be brought into agreement with the right or the ideal law which is found in the sense of right of humanity. BONNO TAPPER","PeriodicalId":346392,"journal":{"name":"The International Journal of Ethics","volume":"1 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1937-07-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"129968321","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
The International Journal of Ethics
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1